DISCOURSE VIII
Delivered to the Students of the Royal Academy, on the Distribution of the Prizes, December 10, 1778.
The Principles of Art,
whether Poetry or Painting, have their Foundation in the Mind; such as Novelty,
Variety, and Contrast; these in their Excess become Defects.‹Simplicity. Its Excess Disagreeable.‹Rules not to
be always observed in their Literal Sense: Sufficient to preserve the Spirit of
the Law.‹Observations on the Prize
Pictures.
GENTLEMEN,
I HAVE recommended in
former discourses, that artists should learn their profession by endeavouring
to form an idea of perfection from the different excellences which lie
dispersed in the various schools of painting. Some difficulty will still occur,
to know what is beauty, and where it may be found: one would wish not to be
obliged to take it entirely on the credit of fame; though to this, I
acknowledge, the younger students must unavoidably submit. Any suspicion in
them of the chance of their being deceived, will have more tendency to obstruct
their advancement, than even an enthusiastic confidence in the perfection of
their models. But to the more advanced in the art, who wish to stand on more
stable and firmer ground, and to establish principles on a stronger foundation
than authority, however venerable or powerful, it may be safely told, that
there is still a higher tribunal, to which those great masters themselves must
submit, and to which indeed every excellence in art must be ultimately
referred. He who is ambitious to enlarge the boundaries of his art must extend
his views, beyond the precepts which are found in books or may be drawn from
the practice of his predecessors, to a knowledge of those precepts in the mind,
those operations of intellectual nature, to which everything that aspires to
please must be proportioned and accommodated.
Poetry having a more
extensive power than our art, exerts its influence over almost all the
passions; among those may be reckoned one of our most prevalent dispositions,
anxiety for the future. Poetry operates by raising our curiosity, engaging the
mind by degrees to take an interest in the event, keeping that event suspended,
and surprising at last with an unexpected catastrophe.
The painter¹s art is more
confined, and has nothing that corresponds with, or perhaps is equivalent to,
this power and advantage of leading the mind on, till attention is totally
engaged. What is done by painting, must be done at one blow; curiosity has
received at once all the satisfaction it can ever have. There are, however, other
intellectual qualities and dispositions which the painter can satisfy and
affect as powerfully as the poet: among those we may reckon our love of
novelty, variety, and contrast; these qualities, on examination, will be found
to refer to a certain activity and restlessness, which has a pleasure and
delight in being exercised and put in motion: art therefore only administers to
those wants and desires of the mind.
It requires no long
disquisition to show, that the dispositions which I have stated actually
subsist in the human mind. Variety reanimates the attention, which is apt to
languish under a continual sameness. Novelty makes a more forcible impression
on the mind, than can be made by the representation of what we have often seen
before; and contrasts rouse the power of comparison by opposition. All this is
obvious; but, on the other hand, it must be remembered, that the mind, though
an active principle, has likewise a disposition to indolence; and though it
loves exercise, loves it only to a certain degree, beyond which it is very
unwilling to be led, or driven; the pursuit therefore of novelty and variety
may be carried to excess. When variety entirely destroys the pleasure
proceeding from uniformity and repetition, and when novelty counteracts and shuts
out the pleasure arising from old habits and customs, they oppose too much the
indolence of our disposition: the mind therefore can bear with pleasure but a
small portion of novelty at a time. The main part of the work must be in the
mode to which we have been used. An affection to old habits and customs I take
to be the predominant disposition of the mind, and novelty comes as an
exception: where all is novelty, the attention, the exercise of the mind is too
violent. Contrast, in the same manner, when it exceeds certain limits, is as
disagreeable as a violent and perpetual opposition; it gives to the senses, in
their progress, a more sudden change than they can bear with pleasure.
It is then apparent, that
those qualities, however they contribute to the perfection of art, when kept
within certain bounds, if they are carried to excess, become defects, and
require correction: a work consequently will not proceed better and better as
it is more varied; variety can never be the groundwork and principle of the
performance‹it must be only employed to recreate and relieve.
To apply these general
observations, which belong equally to all arts, to ours in particular. In a composition, when the objects are
scattered and divided into many equal parts, the eye is perplexed and fatigued,
from not knowing where to rest, where to find the principal action, or which is
the principal figure; for where all are making equal pretensions to notice, all
are in equal danger of neglect.
The expression which is
used very often on these occasions is, the piece wants repose; a word which
perfectly expresses a relief of the mind from that state of hurry and anxiety
which it suffers, when looking at a work of this character.
On the other hand,
absolute unity, that is, a large work, consisting of one group or mass of tight
only, would be as defective as an heroic poem without episode, or any
collateral incidents to recreate the mind with that variety which it always
requires. An instance occurs to me of two painters (Rembrandt and Poussin), of
characters totally opposite to each other in every respect, but in nothing more
than in their mode of composition, and management of light and shadow.
Rembrandt's manner is absolute unity; he often has but one group, and exhibits
little more than one spot of light in the midst of a large quantity of shadow:
if he has a second mass, that second bears no proportion to the principal.
Poussin, on the contrary, has scarce any principal mass of light at all, and
his figures are often too much dispersed, without sufficient attention to place
them in groups.
The conduct of these two
painters is entirely the reverse of what might be expected from their general
style and character; the works of Poussin being as much distinguished for
simplicity, as those of Rembrandt for combination. Even this conduct of Poussin
might proceed from too great an affection to simplicity of another kind; too
great a desire to avoid that ostentation of art, with regard to light and
shadow, on which Rembrandt so much wished to draw the attention: however, each
of them ran into contrary extremes, and it is difficult to determine which is
the most reprehensible, both being equally distant from the demands of nature,
and the purposes of art.
The same just moderation
must be observed in regard to ornaments; nothing will contribute more to
destroy repose than profusion, of whatever kind, whether it consists in the
multiplicity of objects, or the variety and brightness of colours. On the other
hand, a work without ornament, instead of simplicity, to which it makes
pretensions, has rather the appearance of poverty. The degree to which
ornaments are admissible must be regulated by the professed style of the work;
but we may be sure of this truth, ‹that the most ornamental style requires
repose to set off even its ornaments to advantage. I cannot avoid mentioning
here an instance of repose in that faithful and accurate painter of nature,
Shakspeare; the short dialogue between Duncan and Banquo, whilst they are
approaching the gates of Macbeth's castle. Their conversation very naturally
turns upon the beauty of its situation, and the pleasantness of the air: and
Banquo, observing the martlets' nests in every recess of the cornice, remarks,
that where those birds most breed and haunt, the air is delicate. The subject
of this quiet and easy conversation gives that repose so necessary to the mind,
after the tumultuous bustle of the preceding scenes, and perfectly contrasts
the scene of horror that immediately succeeds. It seems as if Shakspeare asked
himself, What is a prince likely to say to his attendants on such an occasion?
The modern writers seem, on the contrary, to be always searching for new
thoughts, such as never could occur to men in the situation represented. This
is also frequently the practice of Homer; who, from the midst of battles and
horrors, relieves and refreshes the mind of the reader, by introducing some
quiet rural image, or picture of familiar domestic life. The writers of every
age and country, where taste has begun to decline, paint and adorn every object
they touch; are always on the stretch; never deviate or sink a moment from the
pompous and the brilliant. Lucan, Statius, and Claudian (as a learned critic
has observed), are examples of this bad taste and want of judgment; they never
soften their tones, or condescend to be natural: all is exaggeration and
perpetual splendour, without affording repose of any kind.
As we are speaking of
excesses, it will not be remote from our purpose to say a few words upon
simplicity; which, in one of the senses in which it is used, is considered as
the general corrector of excess. We shall at present forbear to consider it as
implying that exact conduct which proceeds from an intimate knowledge of simple
unadulterated nature, as it is then only another word for perfection, which
neither stops short of, nor oversteps, reality and truth.
In our inquiry after
simplicity, as in many other inquiries of this nature, we can best explain what
is right, by showing what is wrong; and, indeed, in this case it seems to be
absolutely necessary: simplicity, being only a negative virtue, cannot be
described or defined. We must therefore explain its nature, and show the
advantage and beauty which is derived from it, by showing the deformity which
proceeds from its neglect.
Though instances of this
neglect might be expected to be found in practice, we should not expect to find
in the works of critics precepts that bid defiance to simplicity and everything
that relates to it. De Piles recommends to us portrait-painters to add grace
and dignity to the characters of those whose pictures we draw: so far he is
undoubtedly right; but, unluckily, he descends to particulars, and gives his
own idea of grace and dignity.
³If,² says he, ³you draw
persons of high character and dignity, they ought to be drawn in such an
attitude that the portraits must seem to speak to us of themselves, and, as it
were, to say to us, ŒStop, take notice of me, I am that invincible King,
surrounded by Majesty¹: ŒI am that valiant commander, who struck terror
everywhere¹: ŒI am that great
minister, who knew all the springs of politics¹: ŒI am that magistrate of
consummate wisdom and probity.¹² He goes on in this manner, with all the characters
he can think on. We may contrast the tumour of this presumptuous loftiness with
the natural unaffected air of the portraits of Titian, where dignity, seeming
to be natural and inherent, draws spontaneous reverence, and instead of being
thus vainly assumed, has the appearance of an unalienable adjunct; whereas such
pompous and laboured insolence of grandeur is so far from creating respect,
that it betrays vulgarity and meanness, and new-acquired consequence.
The painters, many of
them at least, have not been backward in adopting the notions contained in
these precepts. The portraits of Rigaud are perfect examples of an implicit
observance of these rules of De Piles; so that though he was a painter of great
merit in many respects, yet that merit is entirely overpowered by a total
absence of simplicity in every sense.
Not to multiply
instances, which might be produced for this purpose, from the works of
history-painters; I shall mention only one,‹a picture which I have seen, of the
Supreme Being by Coypell.
This subject the Roman
Catholic painters have taken the liberty to represent, however indecent the
attempt, and however obvious the impossibility of any approach to an adequate
representation: but here the air and character, which the painter has given,
and he has doubtless given the highest he could conceive, are so degraded by an
attempt at such dignity as De Piles has recommended, that we are enraged at the
folly and presumption of the artist, and consider it as little less than
profanation.
As we have passed to a
neighbouring nation for instances of want of this quality, we must acknowledge,
at the same time, that they have produced great examples of simplicity, in
Poussin and Le Sueur. But as we are speaking of the most refined and subtle
notion of perfection, may we not inquire, whether a curious eye cannot discern
some faults, even in those great men? I can fancy, that even Poussin, by
abhorring that affectation and that want of simplicity, which he observed in
his countrymen, has, in certain particulars, fallen into the contrary extreme, so
far as to approach to a kind of affectation; ‹to what, in writing, would be
called pedantry.
When simplicity, instead
of being a corrector, seems to set up for herself; that is, when an artist
seems to value himself solely upon this quality; such an ostentatious display
of simplicity becomes then as disagreeable and nauseous as any other kind of
affectation. He is, however, in this case, likely enough to sit down contented
with his own work; for though he finds the world look at it with indifference
or dislike, as being destitute of every quality that can recreate or give
pleasure to the mind, yet he consoles himself, that it has simplicity, a beauty
of too pure and chaste a nature to be relished by vulgar minds.
It is in art as in
morals; no character would inspire us with an enthusiastic admiration of his
virtue, if that virtue consisted only in an absence of vice; something more is
required; a man must do more than merely his duty, to be a hero.
Those works of the
ancients, which are in the highest esteem, have something beside mere
simplicity to recommend them. The Apollo, the Venus, the Laocoon, the
Gladiator, have a certain composition of action, have contrasts sufficient to
give grace and energy in a high degree; but it must be confessed of the many
thousand antique statues which we have, that their general characteristic is
bordering at least on inanimate insipidity.
Simplicity, when so very
inartificial as to seem to evade the difficulties of art, is a very suspicious
virtue.
I do not, however, wish
to degrade simplicity from the high estimation in which it has been ever justly
held. It is our barrier against that great enemy to truth and nature,
affectation, which is ever clinging to the pencil, and ready to drop in and
poison everything it touches.
Our love and affection to
simplicity proceeds in a great measure from our aversion to every kind of
affectation. There is likewise another reason why so much stress is laid upon
this virtue; the propensity which artists have to fall into the contrary
extreme; we therefore set a guard on that side which is most assailable. When a
young artist is first told, that his composition and his attitudes must be
contrasted, that he must turn the head contrary to the position of the body, in
order to produce grace and animation; that his outline must be undulating, and
swelling, to give grandeur; and that the eye must be gratified with a variety
of colours; when he is told this, with certain animating words, of spirit,
dignity, energy, grace, greatness of style, and brilliancy of tints, he becomes
suddenly vain of his newly acquired knowledge, and never thinks he can carry
those rules too far. It is then that the aid of simplicity ought to be called
in, to correct the exuberance of youthful ardour.
The same may be said in
regard to colouring, which in its pre-eminence is particularly applied to
flesh. An artist, in his first essay of imitating nature, would make the whole
mass of one colour, as the oldest painters did; till he is taught to observe
not only the variety of tints, which are in the object itself, but the
differences produced by the gradual decline of light to shadow: he then
immediately puts his instruction in practice, and introduces a variety of
distinct colours. He must then be again corrected and told, that though there
is this variety, yet the effect of the whole upon the eye must have the union
and simplicity of the colouring of nature.
And here we may observe
that the progress of an individual student bears a great resemblance to the
progress and advancement of the art itself. Want of simplicity would probably
be not one of the defects of an artist who had studied nature only, as it was
not of the old masters, who lived in the time preceding the great art of
painting; on the contrary, their works are too simple and too inartificial.
The art in its infancy,
like the first work of a student, was dry, hard, and simple. But this kind of
barbarous simplicity would be better named penury, as it proceeds from mere
want; from want of knowledge, want of resources, want of abilities to be
otherwise: their simplicity was the offspring, not of choice, but necessity.
In the second stage they
were sensible of this poverty; and those who were the most sensible of the want
were the best judges of the measure of the supply. There were painters who
emerged from poverty without falling into luxury. Their success induced others,
who probably never would of themselves have had strength of mind to discover
the original defect, to endeavour at the remedy by an abuse; and they ran into
the contrary extreme. But however
they may have strayed, we cannot recommend to them to return to that simplicity
which they have justly quitted; but to deal out their abundance with a more sparing
hand, with that dignity which makes no parade, either of its riches, or of its
art. It is not easy to give a rule which may serve to fix this just and correct
medium; because when we may have fixed, or nearly fixed the middle point, taken
as a general principle, circumstances may oblige us to depart from it, either
on the side of simplicity or on that of variety and decoration.
I thought it necessary in
a former discourse, speaking of the difference of the sublime and ornamental
style of painting, ‹in order to excite your attention to the more manly, noble,
and dignified manner, to leave perhaps an impression too contemptuous of those
ornamental parts of our art, for which many have valued themselves, and many
works are much valued and esteemed.
I said then, what I
thought it was right at that time to say; I supposed the disposition of young
men more inclinable to splendid negligence, than perseverance in laborious
application to acquire correctness; and therefore did as we do in making what
is crooked straight, by bending it the contrary way, in order that it may
remain straight at last.
For this purpose, then,
and to correct excess or neglect of any kind, we may here add, that it is not
enough that a work be learned; it must be pleasing: the painter must add grace
to strength, if he desires to secure the first impression in his favour. Our
taste has a kind of sensuality about it, as well as a love of the sublime; both
these qualities of the mind are to have their proper consequence, as far as
they do not counteract each other; for that is the grand error which much care
ought to be taken to avoid.
There are some rules,
whose absolute authority, like that of our nurses, continues no longer than
while we are in a state of childhood. One of the first rules, for instance,
that I believe every master would give to a young pupil, respecting his conduct
and management of light and shadow, would be what Lionardo da Vinci has
actually given; that you must oppose a light ground to the shadowed side of
your figure, and a dark ground to the light side. If Lionardo had lived to see
the superior splendour and effect which has been since produced by the exactly
contrary conduct, ‹by joining light to light, and shadow to shadow,‹though
without doubt he would have admired it, yet, as it ought not, so probably it would
not, be the first rule with which he would have begun his instructions.
Again: in the artificial
management of the figures, it is directed that they shall contrast each other
according to the rules generally given; that if one figure opposes his front to
the spectator, the next figure is to have his back turned, and that the limbs
of each individual figure be contrasted; that is, if the right leg be put
forward, the right arm is to be drawn back.
It is very proper that
those rules should be given in the Academy; it is proper the young students
should be informed that some research is to be made, and that they should be
habituated to consider every excellence as reducible to principles. Besides, it
is the natural progress of instruction to teach first what is obvious and
perceptible to the senses, and from hence proceed gradually to notions large,
liberal, and complete, such as comprise the more refined and higher excellences
in art. But when students are more advanced, they will find that the greatest beauties
of character and expression are produced without contrast; nay, more, that this
contrast would ruin and destroy that natural energy of men engaged in real
action, unsolicitous of grace. St. Paul preaching at Athens in one of the
cartoons, far from any affected academical contrast of limbs, stands equally on
both legs, and both hands are in the same attitude: add contrast, and the whole
energy and unaffected grace of the figure is destroyed. Elymas the sorcerer
stretches both hands forward in the same direction, which gives perfectly the
expression intended. Indeed you never will find in the works of Raffaelle any
of those schoolboy affected contrasts.
Whatever contrast there is, appears without any seeming agency of art,
by the natural chance of things.
What has been said of the
evil of excesses of all kinds, whether of simplicity, variety, of contrast,
naturally suggests to the painter the necessity of a general inquiry into the
true meaning and cause of rules, and how they operate on those faculties to
which they are addressed: by knowing their general purpose and meaning, he will
often find that he need not confine himself to the literal sense; it will be
sufficient if he preserve the spirit of the law.
Critical remarks are not
always understood without examples: it may not be improper therefore to give
instances where the rule itself, though generally received, is false, or where
a narrow conception of it may lead the artist into great errors.
It is given as a rule by
Fresnoy, that the principal figure of a subject must appear in the midst of
the picture, under the principal light, to distinguish it from the rest. A painter who should think himself obliged
strictly to follow this rule would encumber himself with needless difficulties;
he would be confined to great uniformity of composition, and be deprived of
many beauties which are incompatible with its observance. The meaning of this
rule extends, or ought to extend, no further than this: that the principal
figure should be immediately distinguished at the first glance of the eye; but
there is no necessity that the principal light should fall on the principal
figure, or that the principal figure should be in the middle of the picture. It
is sufficient that it be distinguished by its place, or by the attention of
other figures pointing it out to the spectator. So far is this rule from being
indispensable, that it is very seldom practised, other considerations of
greater consequence often standing in the way. Examples in opposition to this rule are found in the
cartoons, in Christ¹s Charge to Peter, the Preaching of St. Paul, and Elymas
the Sorcerer, who is undoubtedly the principal object in that picture. In none
of those compositions is the principal figure in the midst of the picture. In
the very admirable composition of the Tent of Darius, by Le Brun, Alexander is
not in the middle of the picture, nor does the principal light fall on him; but
the attention of all the other figures immediately distinguishes him, and
distinguishes him more properly; the greatest light falls on the daughter of
Darius, who is in the middle of the picture, where it is more necessary the
principal light should be placed.
It is very extraordinary
that Felibien, who has given a very minute description of this picture, but
indeed such a description as may be rather called panegyric than criticism,
thinking it necessary (according to the precept of Fresnoy) that Alexander
should possess the principal light, has accordingly given it to him; he might
with equal truth have said that he was placed in the middle of the picture, as
he seemed resolved to give this piece every kind of excellence which he
conceived to be necessary to perfection. His generosity is here unluckily
misapplied, as it would have destroyed in a great measure the beauty of the
composition.
Another instance occurs
to me, where equal liberty may be taken in regard to the management of light.
Though the general practice is to make a large mass about the middle of the
picture surrounded by shadow, the reverse may be practised, and the spirit of
the rule may still be preserved. Examples of this principle reversed may be
found very frequently in the works of the Venetian school. In the great
composition of Paul Veronese, the Marriage at Cana, the figures are for the
most part in half shadow; the great light is in the sky; and indeed the general
effect of this picture, which is so striking, is no more than what we often see
in landscapes, in small pictures of fairs and country feasts; but those
principles of light and shadow, being transferred to a large scale, to a space
containing near a hundred figures as large as life, and conducted to all
appearance with as much facility, and with an attention as steadily fixed upon
the whole together, as if it were a small picture immediately under
the eye, the work justly excites our admiration; the difficulty being increased
as the extent is enlarged.
The various modes of
composition are infinite; sometimes it shall consist of one large group in the
middle of the picture, and the smaller groups on each side; or a plain space in
the middle, and the groups of figures ranked round this vacuity.
Whether this principal
broad light be in the middle space of ground, as in the School of Athens, or in
the sky, as in the Marriage at Cana, in the Andromeda, and in most of the
pictures of Paul Veronese; or whether the light be on the groups; whatever mode
of composition is adopted, every variety and licence is allowable: this only is
indisputably necessary, that to prevent the eye from being distracted and
confused by a multiplicity of objects of equal magnitude, those objects,
whether they consist of lights, shadows, or figures, must be disposed in large
masses and groups properly varied and contrasted; that to a certain quantity of
action a proportioned space of plain ground is required; that light is to
be supported by sufficient shadow; and, we may add, that a certain quantity of
cold colours is necessary to give value and lustre to the warm colours: what
those proportions are cannot be so well learnt by precept as by observation on
pictures, and in this knowledge bad pictures will instruct as well as good. Our
inquiry why pictures have a bad effect may be as advantageous as the inquiry
why they have a good effect; each will corroborate the principles that are
suggested by the other.
Though it is not my
business to enter into the detail of our art, yet I must take this opportunity
of mentioning one of the means of producing that great effect which we observe
in the works of the Venetian painters, as I think it is not generally known or
observed. It ought, in my opinion, to be indispensably observed, that the
masses of light in a picture be always of a warm mellow colour, yellow, red, or
a yellowish-white; and that the blue, the grey, or the green colours be kept
almost entirely out of these masses, and be used only to support and set off
these warm colours; and for this purpose, a small proportion of cold colours
will be sufficient.
Let this conduct he
reversed; let the light be cold, and the surrounding colours warm, as we often
see in the works of the Roman and Florentine painters, and it will be out of
the power of art, even in the hands of Rubens or Titian, to make a picture
splendid and harmonious.
Le Brun and Carlo Maratti
were two painters of great merit, and particularly what may be called
academical merit, but were both deficient in this management of colours: the
want of observing this rule is one of the causes of that heaviness of effect
which is so observable in their works. The principal light in the picture of Le
Brun, which I just now mentioned, falls on Statira, who is dressed very
injudiciously in a pale blue drapery: it is true, he has heightened this blue
with gold, but that is not enough; the whole picture has a heavy air, and by no
means answers the expectation raised by the print. Poussin often made a spot of
blue drapery, when the general hue of the picture was inclinable to brown or
yellow; which shows sufficiently, that harmony of colouring was not a part of
the art that had much engaged the attention of that great painter.
The conduct of Titian in
the picture of Bacchus and Ariadne has been much celebrated, and justly, for
the harmony of colouring. To Ariadne is given (say the critics) a red scarf, to
relieve the figure from the sea, which is behind her. It is not for that reason
alone, but for another of much greater consequence; for the sake of the general
harmony and effect of the picture. The figure of Ariadne is separated from the
great group, and is dressed in blue, which, added to the colour of the sea,
makes that quantity of cold colour which Titian thought necessary for the
support and brilliancy of the great group; which group is composed, with very
little exception, entirely of mellow colours. But as the picture in this case
would be divided into two distinct parts, one half cold, and the other warm, it
was necessary to carry some of the mellow colours of the great group into the
cold part of the picture, and a part of the cold into the great group; accordingly
Titian gave Ariadne a red scarf, and to one of the Bacchante a little blue
drapery.
The light of the picture,
as I observed, ought to be of a warm colour; for though white may be used for
the principal light, as was the practice of many of the Dutch and Flemish
painters, yet it is better to suppose that white illumined by the yellow rays
of the setting sun, as was the manner of Titian. The superiority of which
manner is never more striking, than when in a collection of pictures we chance
to see a portrait of Titian's hanging by the side of a Flemish picture (even
though that should be of the hand of Vandyck), which, however admirable in
other respects, becomes cold and grey in the comparison.
The illuminated parts of
objects are in nature of a warmer tint than those that are in the shade: what I
have recommended therefore is no more, than that the same conduct be observed
in the whole, which is acknowledged to be necessary in every individual part.
It is presenting to the eye the same effect as that which it has been
accustomed to feel, which in this case, as in every other, will always produce
beauty; no principle therefore in our art can be more certain, or is derived
from a higher source.
What I just now mentioned
of the supposed reason why Ariadne has part of her drapery red gives me
occasion here to observe, that this favourite quality of giving objects relief,
and which De Piles and all the critics have considered as a requisite of the
utmost importance, was not one of those objects which much engaged the
attention of Titian; painters of an inferior rank have far exceeded him in
producing this effect. This was a great object of attention, when art was in
its infant state; as it is at present with the vulgar and ignorant, who feel
the highest satisfaction in seeing a figure, which, as they say, looks as if
they could walk round it. But however low I may rate this pleasure of
deception, I should not oppose it, did it not oppose itself to a quality of a
much higher kind, by counteracting entirely that fulness of manner which is so
difficult to express in words, but which is found in perfection in the best
works of Correggio, and, we may add, of Rembrandt. This effect is produced by
melting and losing the shadows in a ground still darker than those shadows;
whereas that relief is produced by opposing and separating the ground from the
figure either by light, or shadow, or colour. This conduct of inlaying, as it
may be called, figures on their ground, in order to produce relief, was the
practice of the old painters, such as Andrea Mantegna, Pietro Perugino, and
Albert Dürer; and to these we may add, the first manner of Lionardo da Vinci,
Giorgione, and even Correggio; but these three were among the first who began
to correct themselves in dryness of style, by no longer considering relief as a
principal object. As those two qualities, relief and fulness of effect, can
hardly exist together, it is not very difficult to determine to which we ought
to give the preference. An artist is obliged for ever to hold a balance in his
hand, by which he must determine the value of different qualities; that, when some fault must be committed, he may choose the least.
Those painters who have best understood the art of producing a good effect,
have adopted one principle that seems perfectly conformable to reason; that a
part may be sacrificed for the good of the whole. Thus, whether the masses
consist of light or shadow, it is necessary that they should be compact and of
a pleasing shape: to this end, some parts may be made darker and some lighter,
and reflections stronger than nature would warrant. Paul Veronese took great
liberties of this kind. It is said, that being once asked, why certain figures
were painted in shade, as no cause was seen in the picture itself, he turned off
the inquiry by answering, ³una nuevola che passa,² a cloud is passing which has overshadowed them.
But I cannot give a
better instance of this practice than a picture which I have of Rubens; it is a
representation of a moonlight. Rubens has not only diffused more light over the
picture than is in nature, but has bestowed on it those warm glowing colours by
which his works are so much distinguished. It is so unlike what any other
painters have given us of moonlight, that it might be easily mistaken, if he
had not likewise added stars, for a fainter setting sun. ‹Rubens thought the
eye ought to be satisfied in this case, above all other considerations: he
might indeed have made it more natural, but it would have been at the expense
of what he thought of much greater consequence,‹the harmony proceeding from the
contrast and variety of colours.
This same picture will
furnish us with another instance, where we must depart from nature for a
greater advantage. The moon in this picture does not preserve so great a
superiority in regard to its lightness over the object which it illumines, as
it does in nature; this is likewise an intended deviation, and for the same
reason. If Rubens had preserved the same scale of gradation of light between
the moon and the objects, which is found in nature, the picture must have
consisted of one small spot of light only, and at a little distance from the
picture nothing but this spot would have been seen. It may be said, indeed,
that this being the case, it is a subject that ought not to be painted: but
then, for the same reason, neither armour, nor anything shining, ought ever to
be painted; for though pure white is used in order to represent the greatest
light of shining objects, it will not in the picture preserve the same superiority
over flesh, as it has in nature, without keeping that flesh-colour of a very
low tint. Rembrandt, who thought it of more consequence to paint light than the
objects that are seen by it, has done this in a picture of Achilles which I
have. The head is kept down to a very low tint, in order to preserve this due
gradation and distinction between the armour and the face; the consequence of
which is, that upon the whole the picture is too black. Surely too much is
sacrificed here to this narrow conception of nature: allowing the contrary
conduct a fault, yet it must be acknowledged a less fault, than making a
picture so dark that it cannot be seen without a peculiar light, and then with
difficulty. The merit or demerit of the different conduct of Rubens and
Rembrandt in those instances which I have given, is not to be determined by the
narrow principles of nature, separated from its effect on the human mind.
Reason and common sense tell us, that before, and above all other
considerations, it is necessary that the work should be seen, not only without
difficulty or inconvenience, but with pleasure and satisfaction; and every
obstacle which stands in the way of this pleasure and convenience must be
removed.
The tendency of this
discourse, with the instances which have been given, is not so much to place
the artist above rules, as to teach him their reason; to prevent him from
entertaining a narrow confined conception of art; to clear his mind from a
perplexed variety of rules and their exceptions, by directing his attention to
an intimate acquaintance with the passions and affections of the mind, from
which all rules arise, and to which they are all referable. Art effects its
purpose by their means; an accurate knowledge therefore of those passions and
dispositions of the mind is necessary to him who desires to effect them upon
sure and solid principles.
A complete essay or
inquiry into the connection between the rules of art, and the eternal and
immutable dispositions of our passions, would be indeed going at once to the
foundation of criticism[1]; but I am too well convinced what
extensive knowledge, what subtle and penetrating judgment would be required, to
engage in such an undertaking: it is enough for me, if, in the language of
painters, I have produced a slight sketch of a part of this vast composition,
but that sufficiently distinct to show the usefulness of such a theory, and its
practicability.
Before I conclude, I
cannot avoid making one observation on the pictures now before us. I have
observed, that every candidate has copied the celebrated invention of Timanthes
in hiding the face of Agamemnon in his mantle; indeed such lavish encomiums
have been bestowed on this thought, and that too by men of the highest
character in critical knowledge,‹Cicero, Quintilian, Valerius Maximus, and
Pliny,‹and have been since re-echoed by almost every modern that has written on
the arts, that your adopting it can neither be wondered at, nor blamed. It
appears now to be so much connected with the subject, that the spectator would
perhaps be disappointed in not finding united in the picture what he always
united in his mind, and considered as indispensably belonging to the subject.
But it may be observed, that those who praise this circumstance were not
painters. They use it as an illustration only of their own art; it served their
purpose, and it was certainly not their business to enter into the objections
that lie against it in another art. I fear we have but very scanty means of
exciting those powers over the imagination which make so very considerable and
refined a part of poetry. It is a doubt with me, whether we should even make
the attempt. The chief, if not the only occasion which the painter has for this
artifice, is, when the subject is improper to be more fully represented, either
for the sake of decency, or to avoid what would be disagreeable to be seen; and
this is not to raise or increase the passions, which is the reason that is
given for this practice, but on the contrary to diminish their effect.
It is true, sketches, or
such drawings as painters generally make for their works, give this pleasure of
imagination to a high degree. From a slight undetermined drawing, where the
ideas of the composition and character are, as I may say, only just touched
upon, the imagination supplies more than the painter himself, probably, could
produce; and we accordingly often find that the finished work disappoints the
expectation that was raised from the sketch; and this power of the imagination
is one of the causes of the great pleasure we have in viewing a collection of
drawings by great painters. These general ideas, which are expressed in
sketches, correspond very well to the art often used in poetry. A great part of
the beauty of the celebrated description of Eve in Milton's Paradise Lost,
consists in using only general indistinct expressions, every reader making out
the detail according to his own particular imagination,‹his own idea of beauty,
grace, expression, dignity, or loveliness: but a painter, when he represents Eve
on a canvas, is obliged to give a determined form, and his own idea of beauty
distinctly expressed.
We cannot on this
occasion, nor indeed on any other, recommend an undeterminate manner, or vague
ideas of any kind, in a complete and finished picture. This notion, therefore,
of leaving anything to the imagination, opposes a very fixed and indispensable
rule in our art,‹that everything shall be carefully and distinctly expressed,
as if the painter knew, with correctness and precision, the exact form and
character of whatever is introduced into the picture. This is what with us is
called science and learning: which must not be sacrificed and given up for an
uncertain and doubtful beauty, which, not naturally belonging to our art, will
probably be sought for without success.
Mr. Falconet has
observed, in a note on this passage in his translation of Pliny, that the
circumstance of covering the face of Agamemnon was probably not in consequence
of any fine imagination of the painter,‹which he considers as a discovery of
the critics,‹but merely copied from the description of the sacrifice, as it is
found in Euripides.
The words from which the
picture is supposed to be taken are these: Agamemnon saw Iphigenia advance
towards the fatal altar; he groaned, he turned aside his head, he shed tears,
and covered his face with his robe.
Falconet does not at all
acquiesce in the praise that is bestowed on Timanthes; not only because it is
not his invention, but because he thinks meanly of this trick of concealing,
except in instances of blood, where the objects would be too horrible to be
seen; but, says he, ³in an afflicted father, in a king, in Agamemnon, you, who
are a painter, conceal from me the most interesting circumstance, and then put
me off with sophistry and a veil. You are² (he adds) ³a feeble painter, without
resource: you do not know even those of your art: I care not what veil it is,
whether closed hands, arms raised, or any other action that conceals from me
the countenance of the hero. You think of veiling Agamemnon: you have unveiled
your own ignorance. A painter who represents Agamemnon veiled is as ridiculous
as a poet would be, who in a pathetic situation, in order to satisfy my
expectations, and rid himself of the business, should say, that the sentiments
of his hero are so far above whatever can be said on the occasion, that he
shall say nothing.²
To what Falconet has
said, we may add, that supposing this method of leaving the expression of grief
to the imagination, to be, as it was thought to be, the invention of the
painter, and that it deserves all the praise that has been given it, still it
is a trick that will serve but once; whoever does it a second time will not
only want novelty, but be justly suspected of using artifice to evade
difficulties. If difficulties overcome make a great part of the merit of art,
difficulties evaded can deserve but little commendation.
[1] This was inadvertently said. I did not recollect
the admirable treatise ³On the Sublime and Beautiful.²