On Gusto (1817)
William Hazlitt
Gusto in art is power or
passion defining any object. It is not so difficult to explain this term in
what relates to expression (of which it may be said to be the highest degree)
as in what relates to things without expression, to the natural appearances of
objects, as mere colour or form. In one sense, however, there is hardly any
object entirely devoid of expression, without some character of power belonging
to it, some precise association with pleasure or pain: and it is in giving this
truth of character from the truth of feeling, whether in the highest or lowest
degree, but always in the highest degree of which the subject is capable, that
gusto consists.
There is a gusto in the
colouring of Titian. Not only do his heads seem to think‹his bodies seem to
feel. This is what the Italians mean by the morbidezza of his flesh-colour. It seems sensitive and alive
all over; not merely to have the look and texture of flesh, but the feeling in
itself. For example, the limbs of his female figures have a luxurious softness
and delicacy, which appears conscious of the pleasure of the beholder. As the
objects themselves in nature would produce an impression on the sense, distinct
from every other object, and having something divine in it, which the heart
owns and the imagination consecrates, the objects in the picture preserve the
same impression, absolute, unimpaired, stamped with all the truth of passion,
the pride of the eye, and the charm of beauty. Rubens makes his fleshcolour like
flowers; Albano¹s is like ivory; Titian¹s is like flesh, and like nothing else.
It is as different from that of other painters, as the skin is from a piece of
white or red drapery thrown over it. The blood circulates here and there, the
blue veins just appear, the rest is distinguished throughout only by that sort
of tingling sensation to the eye, which the body feels within itself. This is
gusto. Vandyke¹s flesh-colour, though it has great truth and purity, wants
gusto. It has not the internal character, the living principle in it. It is a
smooth surface, not a warm, moving mass. It is painted without passion, with
indifference. The hand only has been concerned. The impression slides off from
the eye, and does not, like the tones of Titian¹s pencil, leave a sting behind
it in the mind of the spectator. The eye does not acquire a taste or appetite
for what it sees. In a word, gusto in painting is where the impression made on
one sense excites by affinity those of another.
Michael Angelo's forms
are full of gusto. They every where obtrude the sense of power upon the eye.
His limbs convey an idea of muscular strength, of moral grandeur, and even of
intellectual dignity: they are firm, commanding, broad, and massy, capable of
executing with ease the determined purposes of the will. His faces have no
other expression than his figures, conscious power and capacity. They appear
only to think what they shall do, and to know that they can do it. This is what
is meant by saying that his style is hard and masculine. It is the reverse of
Correggio's, which is effeminate. That is, the gusto of Michael Angelo consists
in expressing energy of will without proportionable sensibility, Correggio's in
expressing exquisite sensibility without energy of will. In Correggio's faces
as well as figures we see neither bones nor muscles, but then what a soul is
there, full of sweetness and of grace-pure, playful, soft, angelical! There is
sentiment enough in a hand painted by Correggio to set up a school of history
painters. Whenever we look at the hands of Correggio's women or of Raphael's,
we always wish to touch them.
Again, Titian's
landscapes have a prodigious gusto, both in the colouring and forms. We shall
never forget one that we saw many years ago in the Orleans Gallery of Acteon
hunting. It had a brown, mellow, autumnal look. The sky was of the colour of
stone. The winds seemed to sing through the rustling branches of the trees, and
already you might hear the twanging of bows resound through the tangled mazes
of the wood. Mr. West, we understand, has this landscape. He will know if this
description of it is just. The landscape background of the St. Peter Martyr is
another well-known instance of the power of this great painter to give a
romantic interest and an appropriate character to the objects of his pencil,
where every circumstance adds to the effect of the scene, ‹the bold trunks of
the tall forest trees, the trailing ground plants, with that cold convent spire
rising in the distance, amidst the blue sapphire mountains and the golden sky.
Rubens has a great deal
of gusto in his Fauns and Satyrs, and in all that expresses motion, but in
nothing else. Rembrandt has it in everything; everything in his pictures has a
tangible character. If he puts a diamond in the ear of a Burgomaster's wife, it
is of the first water; and his furs and stuffs are proof against a Russian
winter. Raphael's gusto was only in expression; he had no idea of the character
of anything but the human form. The dryness and poverty of his style in other
respects is a phenomenon in the art. His trees are like sprigs of grass stuck
in a book of botanical specimens. Was it that Raphael never had time to go
beyond the walls of Rome? That he was always in the streets, at church, or in
the bath? He was not one of the Society of Arcadians.1
Claude's landscapes,
perfect as they are, want gusto. This is not easy to explain. They are perfect
abstractions of the visible images of things; they speak the visible language
of nature truly. They resemble a mirror or miscroscope. To the eye only they
are more perfect than any other landscapes that ever were or will be painted;
they give more of nature, as cognizable by one sense alone; but they lay an
equal stress on all visible impressions; they do not interpret one sense by another;
they do not distinguish the character of different objects as we are taught,
and can only be taught, to distinguish them by their effect on the different
senses. That is, his eye wanted imagination: it did not strongly sympathize
with his other faculties. He saw the atmosphere, but he did not feel it. He
painted the trunk of a tree or a rock in the foreground as smooth‹with as
complete an abstraction of the gross, tangible impression, as any other part of
the picture; his trees are perfectly beautiful, but quite immoveable; they have
a look of enchantment. In short, his landscapes are unequalled imitations of
nature, released from its subjection to the elements, ‹as if all objects were
become a delightful fairy vision, and the eye had rarefied and refined away the
other senses.
The gusto in the Greek
statues is of a very singular kind. The sense of perfect form nearly occupies
the whole mind, and hardly suffers it to dwell on any other feeling. It seems
enough for them to be, without acting or suffering. Their forms are ideal,
spiritual. Their beauty is power. By their beauty they are raised above the
frailties of pain or passion; by their beauty they are deified.
The infinite quantity of
dramatic invention in Shakspeare takes from his gusto. The power he delights to
shew is not intense, but discursive. He never insists on any thing as much as
he might, except a quibble. Milton has great gusto. He repeats his blow twice;
grapples with and exhausts his subject. His imagination has a double relish of
its objects, an inveterate attachment to the things he describes, and to the
words describing them.
‹³Or where Chineses drive
With
sails and wind their cany waggons light.²
. . .
³Wild above rule or art, enormous bliss.²2
There is a gusto in
Pope's compliments, in Dryden's satires, and Prior's tales; and among
prose-writers, Boccaccio and Rabelais had the most of it. We will only mention
one other work which appears to us to be full of gusto, and that is the
Beggar's Opera. If it is not, we are altogether mistaken in our notions on this
delicate subject.
[1]
³Raphael not only could not paint a landscape; he could not paint peopl ein a
landscape. He could not have
painted the heads or the figures, or even the dresses of the St. Peter Martyr. His figures have always an in-door look, that is, a set,
determined, voluntary, dramatic character, arising from their own passions, or
a watchfulness of those of others, and want that wild uncertainty of
expression, which is connected with the accidents of nature and the changes of
the elements. He has nothing romantic about him.² (Hazlitt¹s note.)
[2] Paradise
Lost, III.438-39;
V. 297.