Edmund Burke
Essay On Taste (Introductory Discourse)
ON a superficial view, we may seem to
differ very widely from each other in our reasonings, and no less in our
pleasures: but notwithstanding this difference, which I think to be rather
apparent than real, it is probable that the standard both of reason and taste
is the same in all human creatures. For if there were not some principles of
judgment as well as of sentiment common to all mankind, no hold could possibly
be taken either on their reason or their passions, sufficient to maintain the
ordinary correspondence of life. It appears indeed to be generally
acknowledged, that with regard to truth and falsehood there is something fixed.
We find people in their disputes continually appealing to certain tests and
standards, which are allowed on all sides, and are supposed to be established
in our common nature. But there is not the same obvious concurrence in any
uniform or settled principles which relate to taste. It is even commonly
supposed that this delicate and aerial faculty, which seems too volatile to
endure even the chains of a definition, cannot be properly tried by any test,
nor regulated by any standard. There is so continual a call for the exercise of
the reasoning faculty, and it is so much strengthened by perpetual contention,
that certain maxims of right reason seem to be tacitly settled amongst the most
ignorant. The learned have improved on this rude science, and reduced those
maxims into a system. If taste has not been so happily cultivated, it was not
that the subject was barren, but that the labourers were few or negligent; for,
to say the truth, there are not the same interesting motives to impel us to fix
the one, which urge us to ascertain the other. And, after all, if men differ in
their opinion concerning such matters, their difference is not attended with
the same important consequences; else I make no doubt but that the logic of
taste, if I may be allowed the expression, might very possibly be as well
digested, and we might come to discuss matters of this nature with as much
certainty, as those which seem more immediately within the province of mere
reason. And indeed, it is very necessary, at the entrance into such an inquiry
as our present, to make this point as clear as possible; for if taste has no
fixed principles, if the imagination is not affected according to some
invariable and certain laws, our labour is likely to be employed to very little
purpose; as it must be judged a useless, if not an absurd undertaking, to lay
down rules for caprice, and to set up for a legislator of whims and fancies.
The term taste, like all other
figurative terms, is not extremely accurate; the thing which we understand by
it is far from a simple and determinate idea in the minds of most men, and it
is therefore liable to uncertainty and confusion. I have no great opinion of a
definition, the celebrated remedy for the cure of this disorder. For, when we
define, we seem in danger of circumscribing nature within the bounds of our own
notions, which we often take up by hazard, or embrace on trust, or form out of
a limited and partial consideration of the object before us; instead of
extending our ideas to take in all that nature comprehends, according to her
manner of combining. We are limited in our inquiry by the strict laws to which
we have submitted at our setting out.
Circa vilem
patulumque morabimur orbem,
Unde pudor proferre pedem vetat
aut operis lex.
A definition may be very
exact, and yet go but a very little way towards informing us of the nature of
the thing defined; but let the virtue of a definition be what it will, in the
order of things, it seems rather to follow than to precede our inquiry, of
which it ought to be considered as the result. It must be acknowledged, that
the methods of disquisition and teaching may be sometimes different, and on
very good reason undoubtedly; but, for my part, I am convinced that the method
of teaching which approaches most nearly to the method of investigation is
incomparably the best; since, not content with serving up a few barren and
lifeless truths, it leads to the stock on which they grew; it tends to set the
reader himself in the track of invention, and to direct him into those paths in
which the author has made his own discoveries, if he should be so happy as to
have made any that are valuable.
But to cut off all
pretence for cavilling, I mean by the word Taste no more than that faculty or
those faculties of the mind, which are affected with, or which form a judgment
of, the works of imagination and the elegant arts. This is, I think the most
general idea of that word, and what is the least connected with any particular
theory. And my point in this inquiry is, to find whether there are any
principles, on which the imagination is affected, so common to all, so grounded
and certain, as to supply the means of reasoning satisfactorily about them. And
such principles of taste I fancy there are; however paradoxical it may seem to
those, who on a superficial view imagine, that there is so great a diversity of
tastes, both in kind and degree, that nothing can be more indeterminate.
All the natural powers in
man, which I know, that are conversant about external objects, are the senses;
the imagination; and the judgment. And first with regard to the senses. We do
and we must suppose, that as the conformation of their organs is nearly or
altogether the same in all men, so the manner of perceiving external objects is
in all men the same, or with little difference. We are satisfied that what appears
to be light to one eye, appears light to another; that what seems sweet to one
palate, is sweet to another; that what is dark and bitter to this man, is
likewise dark and bitter to that; and we conclude in the same manner of great
and little, hard and soft, hot and cold, rough and smooth, and indeed of all
the natural qualities and affections of bodies. If we suffer ourselves to
imagine, that their senses present to different men different images of things,
this sceptical proceeding will make every sort of reasoning on every subject
vain and frivolous, even that sceptical reasoning itself which had persuaded us
to entertain a doubt concerning the agreement of our perceptions. But as there
will be little doubt that bodies present similar images to the whole species,
it must necessarily be allowed, that the pleasures and the pains which every
object excites in one man, it must raise in all mankind, whilst it operates
naturally, simply, and by its proper powers only; for if we deny this, we must
imagine that the same cause, operating in the same manner, and on subjects of
the same kind, will produce different effects; which would be highly absurd.
Let us first consider this point in the sense of taste, and the rather, as the
faculty in question has taken its name from that sense. All men are agreed to
call vinegar sour, honey sweet, and aloes bitter; and as they are all agreed in
finding these qualities in those objects, they do not in the least differ
concerning their effects with regard to pleasure and pain. They all concur in
calling sweetness pleasant, and sourness and bitterness unpleasant. Here there
is no diversity in their sentiments; and that there is not, appears fully from
the consent of all men in the metaphors which are taken from the sense of taste.
A sour temper, bitter expressions, bitter curses, a bitter fate, are terms well
and strongly understood by all. And we are altogether as well understood when
we say, a sweet disposition, a sweet person, a sweet condition, and the like.
It is confessed, that custom and some other causes have made many deviations
from the natural pleasures or pains which belong to these several tastes: but
then the power of distinguishing between the natural and the acquired relish
remains to the very last. A man frequently comes to prefer the taste of tobacco
to that of sugar, and the flavour of vinegar to that of milk; but this makes no
confusion in tastes, whilst he is sensible that the tobacco and vinegar are not
sweet, and whilst he knows that habit alone has reconciled his palate to these
alien pleasures. Even with such a person we may speak, and with sufficient
precision, concerning tastes. But should any man be found who declares, that to
him tobacco has a taste like sugar, and that he cannot distinguish between milk
and vinegar; or that tobacco and vinegar are sweet, milk bitter, and sugar
sour; we immediately conclude that the organs of this man are out of order, and
that his palate is utterly vitiated. We are as far from conferring with such a
person upon tastes, as from reasoning concerning the relations of quantity with
one who should deny that all the parts together were equal to the whole. We do
not call a man of this kind wrong in his notions, but absolutely mad.
Exceptions of this sort, in either way, do not at all impeach our general rule,
nor make us conclude that men have various principles concerning the relations
of quantity or the taste of things. So that when it is said, taste cannot be
disputed, it can only mean, that no one can strictly answer what pleasure or
pain some particular man may find from the taste of some particular thing. This
indeed cannot be disputed; but we may dispute, and with sufficient clearness
too, concerning the things which are naturally pleasing or disagreeable to the
sense. But when we talk of any peculiar or acquired relish, then we must know
the habits, the prejudices, or the distempers of this particular man, and we
must draw our conclusion from those.
This agreement of mankind
is not confined to the taste solely. The principle of pleasure derived from
sight is the same in all. Light is more pleasing than darkness. Summer, when
the earth is clad in green, when the heavens are serene and bright, is more agreeable
than winter, when everything makes a different appearance. I never remember
that anything beautiful, whether a man, a beast, a bird, or a plant, was ever
shown, though it were to a hundred people, that they did not all immediately
agree that it was beautiful, though some might have thought that it fell short
of their expectation, or that other things were still finer. I believe no man
thinks a goose to be more beautiful than a swan, or imagines that what they
call a Friesland hen excels a peacock. It must be observed, too, that the
pleasures of the sight are not near so complicated, and confused, and altered
by unnatural habits and associations, as the pleasures of the taste are;
because the pleasures of the sight more commonly acquiesce in themselves; and
are not so often altered by considerations which are independent of the sight
itself. But things do not spontaneously present themselves to the palate as
they do to the sight; they are generally applied to it, either as food or as
medicine; and, from the qualities which they possess for nutritive or medicinal
purposes, they often form the palate by degrees, and by force of these
associations. Thus opium is pleasing to Turks, on account of the agreeable
delirium it produces. Tobacco is the delight of Dutchmen, as it diffuses a
torpor and pleasing stupefaction. Fermented spirits please our common people,
because they banish care, and all consideration of future or present evils. All
of these would lie absolutely neglected if their properties had originally gone
no further than the taste; but all these together, with tea and coffee, and
some other things, have passed from the apothecaryıs shop to our tables, and
were taken for health long before they were thought of for pleasure. The effect
of the drug has made us use it frequently; and frequent use, combined with the
agreeable effect, has made the taste itself at last agreeable. But this does
not in the least perplex our reasoning; because we distinguish to the last the
acquired from the natural relish. In describing the taste of an unknown fruit,
you would scarcely say that it had a sweet and pleasant flavour like tobacco,
opium, or garlic, although you spoke to those who were in the constant use of
these drugs, and had great pleasure in them. There is in all men sufficient
remembrance of the original natural causes of pleasure, to enable them to bring
all things offered to their senses to that standard, and to regulate their
feelings and opinions by it. Suppose one who had so vitiated his palate as to take
more pleasure in the taste of opium than in that of butter or honey, to be
presented with a bolus of squills; there is hardly any doubt but that he would
prefer the butter or honey to this nauseous morsel, or to any bitter drug to
which he had not been accustomed; which proves that his palate was naturally
like that of other men in all things, that it is still like the palate of other
men in many things, and only vitiated in some particular points. For in judging
of any new thing, even of a taste similar to that which he has been formed by
habit to like, he finds his palate affected in a natural manner, and on the
common principles. Thus the pleasure of all the senses, of the sight, and even
of the taste, that most ambiguous of the senses, is the same in all, high and
low, learned and unlearned.
Besides the ideas, with
their annexed pains and pleasures, which are presented by the sense; the mind
of man possesses a sort of creative power of its own; either in representing at
pleasure the images of things in the order and manner in which they were
received by the senses, or in combining those images in a new manner, and
according to a different order. This power is called imagination; and to this
belongs whatever is called wit, fancy, invention, and the like. But it must be
observed, that this power of the imagination is incapable of producing anything
absolutely new; it can only vary the disposition of those ideas which it has
received from the senses. Now the imagination is the most extensive province of
pleasure and pain, as it is the region of our fears and our hopes, and of all
our passions that are connected with them; and whatever is calculated to affect
the imagination with these commanding ideas, by force of any original natural
impression, must have the same power pretty equally over all men. For since the
imagination is only the representation of the senses, it can only be pleased or
displeased with the images, from the same principle on which the sense is
pleased or displeased with the realities; and consequently there must be just
as close an agreement in the imaginations as in the senses of men. A little
attention will convince us that this must of necessity be the case.
But in the imagination,
besides the pain or pleasure arising from the properties of the natural object,
a pleasure is perceived from the resemblance which the imitation has to the
original: the imagination, I conceive, can have no pleasure but what results
from one or other of these causes. And these causes operate pretty uniformly
upon all men, because they operate by principles in nature, and which are not
derived from any particular habits or advantages. Mr. Locke very justly and
finely observes of wit, that it is chiefly conversant in tracing resemblances:
he remarks, at the same time, that the business of judgment is rather in
finding differences. It may perhaps appear, on this supposition, that there is
no material distinction between the wit and the judgment, as they both seem to
result from different operations of the same faculty of comparing. But in
reality, whether they are or are not dependent on the same power of the mind,
they differ so very materially in many respects, that a perfect union of wit
and judgment is one of the rarest things in the world. When two distinct
objects are unlike to each other, it is only what we expect; things are in
their common way; and therefore they make no impression on the imagination: but
when two distinct objects have a resemblance, we are struck, we attend to them,
and we are pleased. The mind of man has naturally a far greater alacrity and
satisfaction in tracing resemblances than in searching for differences: because
by making resemblances we produce new images; we unite, we create, we enlarge
our stock; but in making distinctions we offer no food at all to the
imagination; the task itself is more severe and irksome, and what pleasure we
derive from it is something of a negative and indirect nature. A piece of news
is told me in the morning; this, merely as a piece of news, as a fact added to
my stock, gives me some pleasure. In the evening I find there was nothing in
it. What do I gain by this, but the dissatisfaction to find that I have been
imposed upon? Hence it is that men are much more naturally inclined to belief
than to incredulity. And it is upon this principle, that the most ignorant and
barbarous nations have frequently excelled in similitudes, comparisons,
metaphors, and allegories, who have been weak and backward in distinguishing
and sorting their ideas. And it is for a reason of this kind, that Homer and
the Oriental writers, though very fond of similitudes, and though they often
strike out such as are truly admirable, seldom take care to have them exact;
that is, they are taken with the general resemblance, they paint it strongly,
and they take no notice of the difference which may be found between the things
compared.
Now, as the pleasure of
resemblance is that which principally flatters the imagination, all men are
nearly equal in this point, as far as their knowledge of the things represented
or compared extends. The principle of this knowledge is very much accidental,
as it depends upon experience and observation, and not on the strength or
weakness of any natural faculty; and it is from this difference in knowledge,
that what we commonly, though with no great exactness, call a difference in
taste proceeds. A man to whom sculp ture is new, sees a barberıs block, or some
ordinary piece of statuary, he is immediately struck and pleased, because he
sees something like a human figure; and, entirely taken up with this likeness,
he does not at all attend to its defects. No person, I believe, at the first
time of seeing a piece of imitation ever did. Some time after, we suppose that
this novice lights upon a more artificial work of the same nature; he now
begins to look with contempt on what he admired at first; not that he admired
it even then for its unlikeness to a man, but for that general, though
inaccurate, resemblance which it bore to the human figure. What he admired at
different times in these so different figures, is strictly the same; and though
his knowledge is improved, his taste is not altered. Hitherto his mistake was
from a want of knowledge in art; and this arose from his inexperience; but he
may be still deficient from a want of knowledge in nature. For it is possible
that the man in question may stop here, and that the masterpiece of a great
hand may please him no more than the middling performance of a vulgar artist:
and this not for want of better or higher relish, but because all men do not
observe with sufficient accuracy on the human figure to enable them to judge
properly of an imitation of it. And that the critical taste does not depend
upon a superior principle in men, but upon superior knowledge, may appear from
several instances. The story of the ancient painter and the shoemaker is very
well known. The shoemaker set the painter right with regard to some mistakes he
had made in the shoe of one of his figures, and which the painter, who had not
made such accurate observations on shoes, and was content with a general
resemblance, had never observed. But this was no impeachment to the taste of
the painter; it only showed some want of knowledge in the art of making shoes.
Let us imagine, that an anatomist had come into the painterıs working-room. His
piece is in general well done, the figure in question in a good attitude, and
the parts well adjusted to their various movements; yet the anatomist, critical
in his art, may observe the swell of some muscle not quite just in the peculiar
action of the figure. Here the anatomist observes what the painter had not
observed; and he passes by what the shoemaker had remarked. But a want of the
last critical knowledge in anatomy no more reflected on the natural good taste
of the painter or of any common observer of his piece, than the want of an
exact knowledge in the formation of a shoe. A fine piece of a decollated head
of St. John the Baptist was shown to a Turkish emperor; he praised many things,
but he observed one defect; he observed that the skin did not shrink from the
wounded part of the neck. The sultan on this occasion, though his observation
was very just, discovered no more natural taste than the painter who executed
this piece, or than a thousand European connoisseurs, who probably never would
have made the same observation. His Turkish Majesty had indeed been well
acquainted with that terrible spectacle, which the others could only have
represented in their imagination. On the subject of their dislike there is a
difference between all these people, arising from the different kinds and
degrees of their knowledge; but there is something in common to the painter,
the shoemaker, the anatomist, and the Turkish emperor, the pleasure arising
from a natural object, so far as each perceives it justly imitated; the
satisfaction in seeing an agreeable figure; the sympathy proceeding from a
striking and affecting incident. So far as taste is natural, it is nearly
common to all.
In poetry, and other
pieces of imagination, the same parity may be observed. It is true, that one
man is charmed with Don Bellianis, and reads Virgil coldly; whilst another is
transported with the Eneid, and leaves Don Bellianis to children. These two men
seem to have a taste very different from each other; but in fact they differ
very little. In both these pieces, which inspire such opposite sentiments, a
tale exciting admiration is told; both are full of action, both are passionate;
in both are voyages, battles, triumphs, and continual changes of fortune. The
admirer of Don Bellianis perhaps does not understand the refined language of
the Eneid, who, if it was degraded into the style of the Pilgrimıs Progress,
might feel it in all its energy, on the same principle which made him an
admirer of Don Bellianis.
In his favourite author
he is not shocked with the continual breaches of probability, the confusion of
times, the offences against manners, the trampling upon geography; for he knows
nothing of geography and chronology, and he has never examined the grounds of
probability. He perhaps reads of a shipwreck on the coast of Bohemia; wholly
taken up with so interesting an event, and only solicitous for the fate of his
hero, he is not in the least troubled at this extravagant blunder. For why
should he be shocked at a shipwreck on the coast of Bohemia, who does not know
but that Bohemia may be an island in the Atlantic ocean? and after all, what
reflection is this on the natural good taste of the person here supposed?
So far then as taste belongs
to the imagination, its principle is the same in all men; there is no
difference in the manner of their being affected, nor in the causes of the
affection; but in the degree there is a difference, which arises from two
causes principally; either from a greater degree of natural sensibility, or
from a closer and longer attention to the object. To illustrate this by the
procedure of the senses, in which the same difference is found, let us suppose
a very smooth marble table to be set before two men; they both perceive it to
be smooth; and they are both pleased with it because of this quality. So far
they agree. But suppose another, and after that another table, the latter still
smoother than the former, to be set before them. It is now very probable that
these men, who are so agreed upon what is smooth, and in the pleasure from
thence, will disagree when they come to settle which table has the advantage in
point of polish. Here is indeed the great difference between tastes, when men
come to compare the excess or diminution of things which are judged by degree
and not by measure. Nor is it easy, when such a difference arises, to settle
the point, if the excess or diminution be not glaring. If we differ in opinion
about two quantities, we can have recourse to a common measure, which may
decide the question with the utmost exactness; and this, I take it, is what
gives mathematical knowledge a greater certainty than any other. But in things
whose excess is not judged by greater or smaller, as smoothness and roughness,
hardness and softness, darkness and light, the shades of colours, all these are
very easily distinguished when the difference is any way considerable, but not
when it is minute, for want of some common measures, which perhaps may never
come to be discovered. In these nice cases, supposing the acuteness of the
sense equal, the greater attention and habit in such things will have the
advantage. In the question about the tables, the marble-polisher will
unquestionably determine the most accurately. But notwithstanding this want of
a common measure for settling many disputes relative to the senses, and their
representative the imagination, we find that the principles are the same in
all, and that there is no disagreement until we come to examine into the
pre-eminence or difference of things, which brings us within the province of
the judgment.
So long as we are
conversant with the sensible qualities of things, hardly any more than the
imagination seems concerned; little more also than the imagination seems
concerned when the passions are represented, because by the force of natural
sympathy they are felt in all men without any recourse to reasoning, and their
justness recognized in every breast. Love, grief, fear, anger, joy, all these
passions have, in their turns, affected every mind; and they do not affect it
in an arbitrary or casual manner, but upon certain, natural, and uniform
principles. But as many of the works of imagination are not confined to the
representation of sensible objects, nor to efforts upon the passions, but
extend themselves to the manners, the characters, the actions, and designs of
men, their relations, their virtues, and vices, they come within the province
of the judgment, which is improved by attention, and by the habit of reasoning.
All these make a very considerable part of what are considered as the objects
of taste; and Horace sends us to the schools of philosophy and the world for
our instruction in them. Whatever certainty is to be acquired in morality and
the science of life; just the same degree of certainty have we in what relates
to them in the works of imitation. Indeed it is for the most part in our skill
in manners, and in the observances of time and place, and of decency in
general, which is only to be learned in those schools to which Horace
recommends us, that what is called taste, by way of distinction, consists; and
which is in reality no other than a more refined judgment. On the whole it
appears to me, that what is called taste, in its most general acceptation, is
not a simple idea, but is partly made up of a perception of the primary
pleasures of sense, of the secondary pleasures of the imagination, and of the
conclusions of the reasoning faculty, concerning the various relations to
these, and concerning the human passions, manners, and actions. All this is
requisite to form taste, and the ground-work of all these is the same in the
human mind; for as the senses are the great originals of all our ideas, and
consequently of all our pleasures, if they are not uncertain and arbitrary, the
whole ground-work of taste is common to all, and therefore there is a
sufficient foundation for a conclusive reasoning on these matters.
Whilst we consider taste
merely according to its nature and species, we shall find its principles
entirely uniform; but the degree in which these principles prevail in the
several individuals of mankind, is altogether as different as the principles
themselves are similar. For sensibility and judgment, which are the qualities
that compose what we commonly call a taste, vary exceedingly in various people.
From a defect in the former of these qualities arises a want of taste; a
weakness in the latter constitutes a wrong or a bad one. There are some men
formed with feelings so blunt, with tempers so cold and phlegmatic, that they
can hardly be said to be awake during the whole course of their lives. Upon
such persons the most striking objects make but a faint and obscure impression.
There are others so continually in the agitation of gross and merely sensual
pleasures, or so occupied in the low drudgery of avarice, or so heated in the
chase of honours and distinction, that their minds, which had been used
continually to the storms of these violent and tempestuous passions, can hardly
be put in motion by the delicate and refined play of the imagination. These
men, though from a different cause, become as stupid and insensible as the
former; but whenever either of these happen to be struck with any natural
elegance or greatness, or with these qualities in any work of art, they are
moved upon the same principle.
The cause of a wrong
taste is a defect of judgment. And this may arise from a natural weakness of
understanding, (in whatever the strength of that faculty may consist,) or,
which is much more commonly the case, it may arise from a want of proper and
well-directed exercise, which alone can make it strong and ready. Besides that
ignorance, inattention, prejudice, rashness, levity, obstinacy, in short, all
those passions, and all those vices, which pervert the judgment in other
matters, prejudice it no less in this its more refined and elegant province.
These causes produce different opinions upon everything which is an object of
the understanding, without inducing us to suppose that there are no settled
principles of reason. And indeed, on the whole, one may observe that there is
rather less difference upon matters of taste among mankind, than upon most of
those which depend upon the naked reason; and that men are far better agreed on
the excellency of a description in Virgil, than on the truth or falsehood of a
theory of Aristotle.
A rectitude of judgment
in the arts, which may be called a good taste, does in a great measure depend
upon sensibility; because, if the mind has no bent to the pleasures of the
imagination, it will never apply itself sufficiently to works of that species
to acquire a competent knowledge in them. But, though a degree of sensibility
is requisite to form a good judgment, yet a good judgment does not necessarily
arise from a quick sensibility of pleasure; it frequently happens that a very
poor judge, merely by force of a greater complexional sensibility, is more
affected by a very poor piece, than the best judge by the most perfect; for as
everything new, extraordinary, grand, or passionate, is well calculated to
affect such a person, and that the faults do not affect him, his pleasure is
more pure and unmixed; and as it is merely a pleasure of the imagination, it is
much higher than any which is derived from a rectitude of the judgment; the
judgment is for the greater part employed in throwing stumbling-blocks in the
way of the imagination, in dissipating the scenes of its enchantment, and in
tying us down to the disagreeable yoke of our reason: for almost the only
pleasure that men have in judging better than others, consists in a sort of
conscious pride and superiority, which arises from thinking rightly; but then,
this is an indirect pleasure, a pleasure which does not immediately result from
the object which is under contemplation. In the morning of our days, when the
senses are unworn and tender, when the whole man is awake in every part, and
the gloss of novelty fresh upon all the objects that surround us, how lively at
that time are our sensations, but how false and inaccurate the judgments we
form of things? I despair of ever receiving the same degree of pleasure from
the most excellent performances of genius, which I felt at that age from pieces
which my present judgment regards as trifling and contemptible. Every trivial
cause of pleasure is apt to affect the man of too sanguine a complexion: his
appetite is too keen to suffer his taste to be delicate; and he is in all
respects what Ovid says of himself in love,
Molle meum levibus cor est
violabile telis,
Et semper causa est, cur ego
semper amem.
One of this character can never be a
refined judge; never what the comic poet calls elegans formarum spectator. The
excellence and force of a composition must always be imperfectly estimated from
its effect on the minds of any, except we know the temper and character of
those minds. The most powerful effects of poetry and music have been displayed,
and perhaps are still displayed, where these arts are but in a very low and
imperfect state. The rude hearer is affected by the principles which operate in
these arts even in their rudest condition; and he is not skillful enough to
perceive the defects. But as the arts advance towards their perfection, the
science of criticism advances with equal pace, and the pleasure of judges is
frequently interrupted by the faults which are discovered in the most finished compositions.
Before I leave this
subject I cannot help taking notice of an opinion which many persons entertain,
as if the taste were a separate faculty of the mind, and distinct from the
judgment and imagination; a species of instinct, by which we are struck
naturally, and at the first glance, without any previous reasoning, with the
excellencies, or the defects, of a composition. So far as the imagination and
the passions are concerned, I believe it true, that the reason is little
consulted; but where disposition, where decorum, where congruity are concerned,
in short, wherever the best taste differs from the worst, I am convinced that
the understanding operates, and nothing else; and its operation is in reality
far from being always sudden, or, when it is sudden, it is often far from being
right. Men of the best taste, by consideration, come frequently to change these
early and precipitate judgments, which the mind, from its aversion to
neutrality and doubt, loves to form on the spot. It is known that the taste
(whatever it is) is improved exactly as we improve our judgment, by extending
our knowledge, by a steady attention to our object, and by frequent exercise.
They who have not taken these methods, if their taste decides quickly, it is
always uncertainly; and their quickness is owing to their presumption and
rashness, and not to any sudden irradiation, that in a moment dispels all
darkness from their minds. But they who have cultivated that species of
knowledge which makes the object of taste, by degrees, and habitually, attain
not only a soundness, but a readiness of judgment, as men do by the same
methods on all other occasions. At first they are obliged to spell, but at
least they read with ease and with celerity; but this celerity of its operation
is no proof that the taste is a distinct faculty. Nobody, I believe, has
attended the course of a discussion, which turned upon matters within the
sphere of mere naked reason, but must have observed the extreme readiness with
which the whole process of the argument is carried on, the grounds discovered,
the objections raised and answered, and the conclusions drawn from premises,
with a quickness altogether as great as the taste can be supposed to work with;
and yet where nothing but plain reason either is or can be suspected to
operate. To multiply principles for every different appearance, is useless, and
unphilosophical too in a high degree.
This matter might be pursued much further; but it is not the extent of the subject which must prescribe our bounds, for what subject does not branch out to infinity? It is the nature of our particular scheme, and the single point of view in which we consider it, which ought to put a stop to our researches.