Edmund Burke
A
Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas Of the Sublime and Beautiful
(1756)
Of the Passion Caused by the Sublime
THE PASSION caused by the great and sublime in nature, when those causes operate most powerfully, is astonishment; and astonishment is that state of the soul, in which all its motions are suspended, with some degree of horror. In this case the mind is so entirely filled with its object, that it cannot entertain any other, nor by consequence reason on that object which employs it. Hence arises the great power of the sublime, that, far from being produced by them, it anticipates our reasonings, and hurries us on by an irresistible force. Astonishment, as I have said, is the effect of the sublime in its highest degree; the inferior effects are admiration, reverence, and respect.
Terror
NO passion so effectually robs the mind of all its powers of
acting and reasoning as fear. For fear being an apprehension of pain or death, it operates in
a manner that resembles actual pain. Whatever therefore is terrible, with
regard to sight, is sublime too, whether this cause of terror be endued with
greatness of dimensions or not; for it is impossible to look on anything as
trifling, or contemptible, that may be dangerous. There are many animals, who
though far from being large, are yet capable of raising ideas of the sublime,
because they are considered as objects of terror. As serpents and poisonous
animals of almost all kinds. And to things of great dimensions, if we annex an
adventitious idea of terror, they become without comparison greater. A level
plain of a vast extent on land, is certainly no mean idea; the prospect of such
a plain may be as extensive as a prospect of the ocean: but can it ever fill
the mind with anything so great as the ocean itself? This is owing to several
causes; but it is owing to none more than this, that the ocean is an object of
no small terror. Indeed, terror is in all cases whatsoever, either more openly
or latently, the ruling principle of the sublime. Several languages bear a
strong testimony to the affinity of these ideas. They frequently use the same
word, to signify indifferently the modes of astonishment or admiration, and
those of terror. [Greek] is in Greek, either fear or wonder; [Greek] is terrible
or respectable; [Greek], to reverence or to fear. Vereor in Latin, is what [Greek] is in
Greek. The Romans used the verb stupeo, a term which strongly marks the state of an astonished
mind, to express the effect of either of simple fear or of astonishment; the
word attonitus
(thunder-struck) is equally expressive of the alliance of these ideas; and do
not the French étonnement, and the English astonishment and amazement, point out as clearly the kindred
emotions which attend fear and wonder? They who have a more general knowledge
of languages, could produce, I make no doubt, many other and equally striking
examples.
Obscurity
TO make anything very terrible, obscurity [1] seems in general to be necessary.
When we know the full extent of any danger, when we can accustom our eyes to
it, a great deal of the apprehension vanishes. Every one will be sensible of
this, who considers how greatly night adds to our dread, in all cases of
danger, and how much the notions of ghosts and goblins, of which none can form
clear ideas, affect minds which give credit to the popular tales concerning
such sorts of beings. Those despotic governments, which are founded on the
passions of men, and principally upon the passion of fear, keep their chief as
much as may be from the public eye. The policy has been the same in many cases
of religion. Almost all the heathen temples were dark. Even in the barbarous
temples of the Americans at this day, they keep their idol in a dark part of
the hut, which is consecrated to his worship. For this purpose too the Druids
performed all their ceremonies in the bosom of the darkest woods, and in the
shade of the oldest and most spreading oaks. No person seems better to have
understood the secret of heightening, or of setting terrible things, if I may
use the expression, in their strongest light, by the force of a judicious
obscurity, than Milton. His description of Death in the second book is
admirably studied; it is astonishing with what a gloomy pomp, with what a
significant and expressive uncertainty of strokes and colouring, he has
finished the portrait of the king of terrors:
‹The other shape,
If shape it might be called that shape had none
Distinguishable, in member, joint, or limb;
Or substance might be called that shadow seemed;
For each seemed either; black he stood as night;
Fierce as ten furies; terrible as hell;
And shook a deadly dart. What seemed his head
The likeness of a kingly crown had on.
In this description all is dark, uncertain, confused, terrible,
and sublime to the last degree.
Of the Difference Between Clearness and Obscurity with Regard
to the Passions
IT is one thing to make an idea clear, and another to make it affecting to the imagination. If I make a
drawing of a palace, or a temple, or a landscape, I present a very clear idea
of those objects; but then (allowing for the effect of imitation, which is
something) my picture can at most affect only as the palace, temple, or
landscape would have affected in the reality. On the other hand, the most
lively and spirited verbal description I can give raises a very obscure and
imperfect idea of
such objects; but then it is in my power to raise a stronger emotion by the description than I could do by
the best painting. This experience constantly evinces. The proper manner of
conveying the affections of the mind from one to another, is by words; there is a great
insufficiency in all other methods of communication; and so far is a clearness
of imagery from being absolutely necessary to an influence upon the passions,
that they may be considerably operated upon, without presenting any image at
all, by certain sounds adapted to that purpose; of which we have a sufficient
proof in the acknowledged and powerful effects of instrumental music. In
reality, a great clearness helps but little towards affecting the passions, as
it is in some sort an enemy to all enthusiasms whatsoever.
The Same Subject Continued
THERE are two verses in Horace¹s Art of Poetry, that seem to
contradict this opinion; for which reason I shall take a little more pains in
clearing it up. The verses are,
Segnius irritant animos demissa per aures,
Quam quæ sunt oculis subjecta fidelibus.
On this the Abbé du Bos founds a criticism, wherein he gives
painting the preference to poetry in the article of moving the passions;
principally on account of the greater clearness of the ideas it represents. I believe
this excellent judge was led into this mistake (if it be a mistake) by his
system; to which he found it more conformable than I imagine it will be found
by experience. I know several who admire and love painting, and yet who regard
the objects of their admiration in that art with coolness enough in comparison
of that warmth with which they are animated by affecting pieces of poetry or
rhetoric. Among the common sort of people, I never could perceive that painting
had much influence on their passions. It is true, that the best sorts of
painting, as well as the best sorts of poetry, are not much understood in that
sphere. But it is most certain, that their passions are very strongly roused by
a fanatic preacher, or by the ballads of Chevy-chase, or the Children in the
Wood, and by other little popular poems and tales that are current in that rank
of life. I do not know of any paintings, bad or good, that produce the same
effect. So that poetry, with all its obscurity, has a more general, as well as
a more powerful, dominion over the passions, than the other art. And I think
there are reasons in nature, why the obscure idea, when properly conveyed,
should be more affecting than the clear. It is our ignorance of things that
causes all our admiration, and chiefly excites our passions. Knowledge and
acquaintance make the most striking causes affect but little. It is thus with
the vulgar; and all men are as the vulgar in what they do not understand. The
ideas of eternity and infinity are among the most affecting we have; and yet
perhaps there is nothing of which we really understand so little, as of
infinity and eternity. We do not anywhere meet a more sublime description than
this justly celebrated one of Milton, wherein he gives the portrait of Satan
with a dignity so suitable to the subject:
‹He above the rest
In shape and gesture proudly eminent
Stood like a tower; his form had yet not lost
All her original brightness, nor appeared
Less than archangel ruined, and th¹ excess
Of glory obscured: as when the sun new risen
Looks through the horizontal misty air
Shorn of his beams; or from behind the moon
In dim eclipse disastrous twilight sheds
On half the nations; and with fear of change
Perplexes monarchs.‹
Here is a very noble picture; and in what does this poetical
picture consist? In images of a tower, an archangel, the sun rising through
mists, or in an eclipse, the ruin of monarchs, and the revolutions of kingdoms.
The mind is hurried out of itself, by a crowd of great and confused images;
which affect because they are crowded and confused. For, separate them, and you
lose much of the greatness; and join them, and you infallibly lose the clearness.
The images raised by poetry are always of this obscure kind; though in general
the effects of poetry are by no means to be attributed to the images it raises;
which point we shall examine more at large hereafter. But
painting, when we have allowed for the pleasure of imitation, can only affect
simply by the images it presents; and even in painting, a judicious obscurity
in some things contributes to the effect of the picture; because the images in
painting are exactly similar to those in nature; and in nature, dark, confused,
uncertain images have a greater power on the fancy to form the grander
passions, than those have which are more clear and determinate. But where and
when this observation may be applied to practice, and how far it shall be extended,
will be better deduced from the nature of the subject, and from the occasion,
than from any rules that can be given.
I am sensible that this idea has met with opposition, and is
likely still to be rejected by several. But let it be considered, that hardly
anything can strike the mind with its greatness, which does not make some sort
of approach towards infinity; which nothing can do whilst we are able to
perceive its bounds; but to see an object distinctly, and to perceive its
bounds, is one and the same thing. A clear idea is therefore another name for a
little idea. There is a passage in the book of Job amazingly sublime, and this
sublimity is principally due to the terrible uncertainty of the thing
described: In thoughts from the visions of the night, when deep sleep
falleth upon men, fear came upon me, and trembling, which made all my bones to
shake. Then a spirit passed before my face; the hair of my flesh stood up. It stood still, but I could not
discern the form thereof: an image was before mine eyes, there was silence,
and I heard a voice,‹Shall mortal man be more just than God? We are first prepared with the utmost
solemnity for the vision; we are first terrified, before we are let even into
the obscure cause of our emotion; but when this grand cause of terror makes it
appearance, what is it? Is it not wrapt up in the shades of its own
incomprehensible darkness, more awful, more striking, more terrible, than the
liveliest description, than the clearest painting, could possibly represent it?
When painters have attempted to give us clear representations of these very
fanciful and terrible ideas, they have, I think, almost always failed; insomuch
that I have been at a loss, in all the pictures I have seen of hell, to
determine whether the painter did not intend something ludicrous. Several
painters have handled a subject of this kind, with a view of assembling as many
horrid phantoms as their imagination could suggest; but all the designs I have
chanced to meet of the temptation of St. Anthony were rather a sort of odd,
wild grotesques, than anything capable of producing a serious passion. In all
these subjects poetry is very happy. Its apparitions, its chimeras, its
harpies, its allegorical figures, are grand and affecting; and though Virgil¹s
Fame and Homer¹s Discord are obscure, they are magnificent figures. These
figures in painting would be clear enough, but I fear they might become
ridiculous.
Power
BESIDES those things which directly suggest the idea of danger, and those
which produce a similar effect from a mechanical cause, I know of nothing
sublime, which is not some modification of power. And this branch rises, as
naturally as the other two branches, from terror, the common stock of
everything that is sublime. The idea of power, at first view, seems of the
class of those indifferent ones, which may equally belong to pain or to
pleasure. But in reality, the affection, arising from the idea of vast power,
is extremely remote from that neutral character. For first, we must remember,
that the idea of pain, in its highest degree, is much stronger than the highest
degree of pleasure; and that it preserves the same superiority through all the
subordinate gradations. From hence it is, that where the chances for equal
degrees of suffering or enjoyment are in any sort equal, the idea of the
suffering must always be prevalent. And indeed the ideas of pain, and, above
all, of death, are so very affecting, that whilst we remain in the presence of
whatever is supposed to have the power of inflicting either, it is impossible
to be perfectly free from terror. Again, we know by experience, that, for the
enjoyment of pleasure, no great efforts of power are at all necessary; nay, we
know, that such efforts would go a great way towards destroying our satisfaction:
for pleasure must be stolen, and not forced upon us; pleasure follows the will;
and therefore we are generally affected with it by many things of a force
greatly inferior to our own. But pain is always inflicted by a power in some
way superior, because we never submit to pain willingly. So that strength,
violence, pain, and terror, are ideas that rush in upon the mind together. Look
at a man, or any other animal of prodigious strength, and what is your idea
before reflection? Is it that this strength will be subservient to you, to your
ease, to your pleasure, to your interest in any sense? No; the emotion you feel
is, lest this enormous strength should be employed to the purposes of rapine
and destruction. That power derives all its sublimity from the terror with
which it is generally accompanied, will appear evidently from its effect in the
very few cases, in which it may be possible to strip a considerable degree of
strength of its ability to hurt. When you do this, you spoil it of everything
sublime, and it immediately becomes contemptible. An ox is a creature of vast
strength; but he is an innocent creature, extremely serviceable, and not at all
dangerous; for which reason the idea of an ox is by no means grand. A bull is
strong too: but his strength is of another kind; often very destructive, seldom
(at least amongst us) of any use in our business; the idea of a bull is
therefore great, and it has frequently a place in sublime descriptions, and
elevating comparisons. Let us look at another strong animal, in the two
distinct lights in which we may consider him. The horse in the light of a
useful beast, fit for the plough, the road, the draft; in every social, useful
light, the horse has nothing sublime: but is it thus that we are affected with
him, whose neck is clothed with thunder, the glory of whose nostrils is
terrible, who swalloweth the ground with fierceness and rage, neither believeth
that it is the sound of the trumpet? In this description, the useful character of the horse entirely
disappears, and the terrible and sublime blaze out together. We have
continually about us animals of a strength that is considerable, but not
pernicious. Amongst these we never look for the sublime; it comes upon us in
the gloomy forest, and in the howling wilderness, in the form of the lion, the
tiger, the panther, or rhinoceros. Whenever strength is only useful, and
employed for our benefit or our pleasure, then it is never sublime: for nothing
can act agreeably to us, that does not act in conformity to our will; but to
act agreeably to our will, it must be subject to us, and therefore can never be
the cause of a grand and commanding conception. The description of the wild
ass, in Job, is worked up into no small sublimity, merely by insisting on his
freedom, and his setting mankind at defiance; otherwise the description of such
an animal could have had nothing noble in it. Who hath loosed (says he) the bands of the wild
ass? whose house I have made the wilderness, and the barren land his dwellings.
He scorneth the multitude of the city, neither regardeth he the voice of the
driver. The range of the mountains is his pasture. The magnificent description of the
unicorn and of leviathan, in the same book, is full of the same heightening
circumstances: Will the unicorn be willing to serve thee? canst thou bind
the unicorn with his band in the furrow? wilt thou trust him because his
strength is great?‹Canst thou draw out leviathan with an hook?‹will he make a
covenant with thee? wilt thou take him for a servant for ever? shall not one be
cast down even at the sight of him? In short, wheresoever we find strength, and in what light soever
we look upon power we shall all along observe the sublime the concomitant of
terror, and contempt the attendant on a strength that is subservient and
innoxious. The race of dogs, in many of their kinds, have generally a competent
degree of strength and swiftness; and they exert these and other valuable
qualities which they possess, greatly to our convenience and pleasure. Dogs are
indeed the most social, affectionate, and amiable animals of the whole brute
creation; but love approaches much nearer to contempt than is commonly
imagined; and accordingly, though we caress dogs, we borrow from them an
appellation of the most despicable kind, when we employ terms of reproach; and
this appellation is the common mark of the last vileness and contempt in every
language. Wolves have not more strength than several species of dogs; but, on
account of their unmanageable fierceness, the idea of a wolf is not despicable;
it is not excluded from grand descriptions and similitudes. Thus we are
affected by strength, which is natural power. The power which arises from institution in kings
and commanders, has the same connexion with terror. Sovereigns are frequently
addressed with the title of dread majesty. And it may be observed, that young persons, little
acquainted with the world, and who have not been used to approach men in power,
are commonly struck with an awe which takes away the free use of their
faculties. When I prepared my seat in the street, (says Job,) the young men saw me,
and hid themselves.
Indeed, so natural is this timidity with regard to power, and so strongly does
it inhere in our constitution, that very few are able to conquer it, but by
mixing much in the business of the great world, or by using no small violence
to their natural dispositions. I know some people are of opinion, that no awe,
no degree of terror, accompanies the idea of power; and have hazarded to
affirm, that we can contemplate the idea of God himself without any such
emotion. I purposely avoided, when I first considered this subject, to
introduce the idea of that great and tremendous Being, as an example in an
argument so light as this; though it frequently occurred to me, not as an objection
to, but as a strong confirmation of, my notions in this matter. I hope, in what
I am going to say, I shall avoid presumption, where it is almost impossible for
any mortal to speak with strict propriety. I say then that whilst we consider
the Godhead merely as he is an object of the understanding, which forms a
complex idea of power, wisdom, justice, goodness, all stretched to a degree far
exceeding the bounds of our comprehension, whilst we consider the Divinity in
this refined and abstracted light, the imagination and passions are little or
nothing affected. But because we are bound, by the condition of our nature, to
ascend to these pure and intellectual ideas, through the medium of sensible
images, and to judge of these divine qualities by their evident acts and
exertions, it becomes extremely hard to disentangle our idea of the cause from
the effect by which we are led to know it. Thus when we contemplate the Deity,
his attributes and their operation, coming united on the mind, form a sort of sensible
image, and as such are capable of affecting the imagination. Now, though in a
just idea of the Deity perhaps none of his attributes are predominant, yet, to
our imagination, his power is by far the most striking. Some reflection, some
comparing, is necessary to satisfy us of his wisdom, his justice, and his
goodness. To be struck with his power, it is only necessary that we should open
our eyes. But whilst we contemplate so vast an object, under the arm, as it
were, of almighty power, and invested upon every side with omnipresence, we
shrink into the minuteness of our own nature, and are, in a manner, annihilated
before him. And though a consideration of his other attributes may relieve, in
some measure, our apprehensions; yet no conviction of the justice with which it
is exercised, nor the mercy with which it is tempered, can wholly remove the
terror that naturally arises from a force which nothing can withstand. If we
rejoice, we rejoice with trembling: and even whilst we are receiving benefits,
we cannot but shudder at a power which can confer benefits of such mighty
importance. When the prophet David contemplated the wonders of wisdom and power
which are displayed in the economy of man, he seems to be struck with a sort of
divine horror, and cries out, Fearfully and wonderfully am I made! An heathen poet has a sentiment of a
similar nature; Horace looks upon it as the last effort of philosophical
fortitude, to behold without terror and amazement, this immense and glorious
fabric of the universe:
Hunc solem, et stellas, et decedentia certis
Tempora momentis, sunt qui formidine nulla
Imbuti spectent.
Lucretius is a poet not to be suspected of giving way to
superstitious terrors; yet when he supposes the whole mechanism of nature laid
open by the master of his philosophy, his transport on this magnificent view,
which he has represented in the colours of such bold and lively poetry, is
overcast with a shade of secret dread and horror:
His ibi me rebus quædam divina voluptas
Percipit, atque horror; quod sic Natura, tua vi
Tam manifesta patens, ex omni parte retecta est.
But the Scripture alone can supply ideas answerable to the majesty
of this subject. In the Scripture, wherever God is represented as appearing or
speaking, everything terrible in nature is called up to heighten the awe and
solemnity of the Divine presence. The Psalms, and the prophetical books, are
crowded with instances of this kind. The earth shook, (says the psalmist), the heavens
also dropped atthe presence of the Lord. And, what is remarkable, the painting pre serves the
same character, not only when he is supposed descending to take vengeance upon
the wicked, but even when he exerts the like plenitude of power in acts of
beneficence to mankind. Tremble, thou earth! at the presence of the Lord; at
the presence of God of Jacob; which turned the rock into standing water, the
flint into a fountain of waters! It were endless to enumerate all the passages, both in the sacred
and profane writers, which establish the general sentiment of mankind,
concerning the inseparable union of a sacred and reverential awe, with our
ideas of the Divinity. Hence the common maxim, Primus in orbe deos fecit
timor. This maxim may
be, as I believe it is, false with regard to the origin of religion. The maker
of the maxim saw how inseparable these ideas were, without considering that the
notion of some great power must be always precedent to our dread of it. But
this dread must necessarily follow the idea of such a power, when it is once
excited in the mind. It is on this principle that true religion has, and must
have, so large a mixture of salutary fear; and that false religions have
generally nothing else but fear to support them. Before the Christian religion
had, as it were, humanized the idea of the Divinity, and brought it somewhat
nearer to us, there was very little said of the love of God. The followers of
Plato have something of it, and only something; the other writers of pagan
antiquity, whether poets or philosophers, nothing at all. And they who consider
with what infinite attention, by what a disregard of every perishable object,
through what long habits of piety and contemplation, it is that any man is able
to attain an entire love and devotion to the Deity, will easily perceive, that
it is not the first, the most natural and the most striking, effect which
proceeds from that idea. Thus we have traced power through its several
gradations unto the highest of all, where our imagination is finally lost; and
we find terror, quite throughout the progress, its inseparable companion, and
growing along with it, as far as we can possibly trace them. Now as power is
undoubtedly a capital source of the sublime, this will point out evidently from
whence its energy is derived, and to what class of ideas we ought to unite it.
Privation
ALL general privations are great, because they are all terrible; Vacuity, Darkness, Solitude, and Silence. With what a fire of imagination, yet
with what severity of judgment, has Virgil amassed all these circumstances,
where he knows that all the images of a tremendous dignity ought to be united,
at the mouth of hell! where, before he unlocks the secrets of the great deep,
he seems to be seized with a religious horror, and to retire astonished at the
boldness of his own designs:
Dii, quibus imperium est animarum, umbræque‹silentes!
Et Chaos, et Phlegethon, loca nocte silentia late,
Sit mihi fas audita loqui; sit, numine vestro,
Pandere res alta terra et caligine mersas.
Ibant
obscuri, sola sub
nocte, per umbram,
Perque domos Ditis vacuas, et inania regna.
Ye subterraneous gods, whose awful sway
The gliding ghosts and silent shades obey;
O Chaos hoar! and Phlegethon profound!
Whose solemn empire stretches wide around;
Give me, ye great, tremendous powers, to tell
Of scenes and wonders in the depth of hell:
Give me your mighty secrets to display
From those black realms of darkness to the day.‹PITT.
Obscure
they went through dreary shades that led
Along the waste dominions of the dead.‹DRYDEN.
Vastness
GREATNESS of dimension is a powerful cause of the sublime. This is
too evident, and the observation too common, to need any illustration: it is
not so common to consider in what ways greatness of dimension, vastness of
extent or quantity, has the most striking effect. For certainly, there are ways
and modes, wherein the same quantity of extension shall produce greater effects
than it is found to do in others. Extension is either in length, height, or
depth. Of these the length strikes least; an hundred yards of even ground will
never work such an effect as a tower an hundred yards high, or a rock or
mountain of that altitude. I am apt to imagine likewise, that height is less
grand than depth; and that we are more struck at looking down from a precipice,
than looking up at an object of equal height; but of that I am not very
positive. A perpendicular has more force in forming the sublime, than an
inclined plane; and the effects of a rugged and broken surface seem stronger
than where it is smooth and polished. It would carry us out of our way to enter
in this place into the cause of these appearances; but certain it is they
afford a large and fruitful field of speculation. However, it may not be amiss
to add to these remarks upon magnitude, that, as the great extreme of dimension
is sublime, so the last extreme of littleness is in some measure sublime
likewise: when we attend to the infinite divisibility of matter, when we pursue
animal life into these excessively small, and yet organized beings, that escape
the nicest inquisition of the sense; when we push our discoveries yet downward,
and consider those creatures so many degrees yet smaller, and the still
diminishing scale of existence, in tracing which the imagination is lost as
well as the sense; we become amazed and confounded at the wonders of
minuteness; nor can we distinguish in its effects this extreme of littleness
from the vast itself. For division must be infinite as well as addition;
because the idea of a perfect unity can no more be arrived at, than that of a complete
whole, to which nothing may be added.
Infinity
ANOTHER source of the sublime is infinity; if it does not rather belong to the
last. Infinity has a tendency to fill the mind with that sort of delightful
horror, which is the most genuine effect and truest test of the sublime. There
are scarce any things which can become the objects of our senses, that are
really and in their own nature infinite. But the eye not being able to perceive
the bounds of many things, they seem to be infinite, and they produce the same
effects as if they were really so. We are deceived in the like manner, if the
parts of some large object are so continued to any indefinite number, that the
imagination meets no check which may hinder its extending them at pleasure.
Whenever we repeat any idea frequently, the mind, by a sort of
mechanism, repeats it long after the first cause has ceased to operate. 1 After
whirling about, when we sit down, the objects about us still seem to whirl.
After a long succession of noises, as the fall of waters, or the beating of
forge-hammers, the hammers beat and the water roars in the imagination long
after the first sounds have ceased to affect it; and they die away at last by
gradations which are scarcely perceptible. If you hold up a straight pole, with
your eye to one end, it will seem extended to a length almost incredible. Place
a number of uniform and equi-distant marks on this pole, they will cause the
same deception, and seem multiplied without end. The senses, strongly affected
in some one manner, cannot quickly change their tenor, or adapt themselves to
other things; but they continue in their old channel until the strength of the
first mover decays. This is the reason of an appearance very frequent in
madmen; that they remain whole days and nights, sometimes whole years, in the
constant repetition of some remark, some complaint, or song; which having
struck powerfully on their disordered imagination in the beginning of their
phrensy, every repetition reinforces it with new strength; and the hurry of
their spirits, unrestrained by the curb of reason, continues it to the end of
their lives.
Succession and Uniformity
SUCCESSION and uniformity of parts are what constitute the artificial infinite. 1.
Succession; which
is requisite that the parts may be continued so long and in such a direction,
as by their frequent impulses on the sense to impress the imagination with an
idea of their progress beyond their actual limits. 2 Uniformity; because if the figures of the parts
should be changed, the imagination at every change finds a check; you are
presented at every alteration with the termination of one idea, and the
beginning of another; by which means it becomes impossible to continue that
uninterrupted progression, which alone can stamp on bounded objects the
character of infinity. [1] It is in this kind of artificial
infinity, I believe, we ought to look for the cause why a rotund has such a
noble effect. For in a rotund, whether it be a building or a plantation, you
can nowhere fix a boundary; turn which way you will, the same object still
seems to continue, and the imagination has no rest. But the parts must be
uniform, as well as circularly disposed, to give this figure its full force;
because any difference, whether it be in the disposition, or in the figure, or
even in the color of the parts, is highly prejudicial to the idea of infinity,
which every change must check and interrupt, at every alteration commencing a
new series. On the same principles of succession and uniformity, the grand appearance
of the ancient heathen temples, which were generally oblong forms, with a range
of uniform pillars on every side, will be easily accounted for. From the same
cause also may be derived the grand effect of the aisles in many of our own old
cathedrals. The form of a cross used in some churches seems to me not so
eligible as the parallelogram of the ancients; at least, I imagine it is not so
proper for the outside. For, supposing the arms of the cross every way equal,
if you stand in a direction parallel to any of the side walls, or colonnades,
instead of a deception that makes the building more extended than it is, you
are cut off from a considerable part (two-thirds) of its actual length; and to prevent all
possibility of progression, the arms of the cross, taking a new direction, make
a right angle with the beam, and thereby wholly turn the imagination from the
repetition of the former idea. Or suppose the spectator placed where he may
take a direct view of such a building, what will be the consequence? The
necessary consequence will be, that a good part of the basis of each angle
formed by the intersection of the arms of the cross, must be inevitably lost;
the whole must of course assume a broken, unconnected figure; the lights must
be unequal, here strong, and there weak; without that noble gradation which the
perspective always effects on parts disposed uninterruptedly in a right line.
Some or all of these objections will lie against every figure of a cross, in
whatever view you take it. I exemplified them in the Greek cross, in which
these faults appear the most strongly; but they appear in some degree in all
sorts of crosses. Indeed there is nothing more prejudicial to the grandeur of
buildings, than to abound in angles; a fault obvious in many; and owing to an
inordinate thirst for variety, which, whenever it prevails, is sure to leave
very little true taste.
Note 1.
Mr. Addison, in the Spectator, concerning the pleasures of imagination, thinks
it is because in the rotund at one glance you see half the building. This I do
not imagine to be the real cause.
Magnitude in Building
TO the sublime in building, greatness of dimension seems
requisite; for on a few parts, and those small, the imagination cannot rise to
any idea of infinity. No greatness in the manner can effectually compensate for
the want of proper dimensions. There is no danger of drawing men into
extravagant designs by this rule; it carries its own caution along with it.
Because too great a length in buildings destroys the purpose of greatness,
which it was intended to promote; the perspective will lessen it in height as
it gains in length; and will bring it at last to a point; turning the whole
figure into a sort of triangle, the poorest in its effect of almost any figure
that can be presented to the eye. I have ever observed, that colonnades and
avenues of trees of a moderate length, were, without comparison, far grander,
than when they were suffered to run to immense distances. A true artist should
put a generous deceit on the spectators, and effect the noblest designs by easy
methods. Designs that are vast only by their dimensions, are always the sign of
a common and low imagination. No work of art can be great, but as it deceives;
to be otherwise is the prerogative of nature only. A good eye will fix the
medium betwixt an excessive length or height, (for the same objection lies
against both,) and a short or broken quantity; and perhaps it might be
ascertained to a tolerable degree of exactness, if it was my purpose to descend
far into the particulars of any art.
Infinity in Pleasing Objects
INFINITY, though of another kind, causes much of our pleasure in
agreeable, as well as of our delight in sublime, images. The spring is the
pleasantest of the seasons; and the young of most animals, though far from
being completely fashioned, afford a more agreeable sensation than the
full-grown; because the imagination is entertained with the promise of
something more, and does not acquiesce in the present object of the sense. In
unfinished sketches of drawing, I have often seen something which pleased me
beyond the best finishing; and this I believe proceeds from the cause I have
just now assigned.
Difficulty
ANOTHER source of greatness is Difficulty. When any work seems to have required
immense force and labor to effect it, the idea is grand. Stonehenge, neither
for disposition nor ornament, has anything admirable; but those huge rude
masses of stone, set on end, and piled each on other, turn the mind on the
immense force necessary for such a work. Nay, the rudeness of the work
increases this cause of grandeur, as it excludes the idea of art and
contrivance; for dexterity produces another sort of effect, which is different
enough from this. 1
Magnificence
Magnificence is likewise a source of the sublime. A great profusion of things,
which are splendid or valuable in themselves, is magnificent. The starry heaven, though it occurs
so very frequently to our view, never fails to excite an idea of grandeur. This
cannot be owing to the stars themselves, separately considered. The number is
certainly the cause. The apparent disorder augments the grandeur, for the
appearance of care is highly contrary to our idea of magnificence. Besides, the
stars lie in such apparent confusion, as makes it impossible on ordinary
occasions to reckon them. This gives them the advantage of a sort of infinity.
In works of art, this kind of grandeur, which consists in multitude, is to be
very courteously admitted; because a profusion of excellent things is not to be
attained, or with too much difficulty; and because in many cases this splendid
confusion would destroy all use, which should be attended to in most of the
works of art with the greatest care; besides, it is to be considered, that
unless you can produce an appearance of infinity by your disorder, you will
have disorder only without magnificence. There are, however, a sort of
fireworks, and some other things, that in this way succeed well, and are truly
grand. There are also many descriptions in the poets and orators, which owe
their sublimity to a richness and profusion of images, in which the mind is so
dazzled as to make it impossible to attend to that exact coherence and
agreement of the allusions, which we should require on every other occasion. I
do not now remember a more striking example of this, than the description which
is given of the king¹s army in the play of Henry the Fourth:
‹All furnished, all in arms,
All plumed like ostriches that with the wind
Baited like eagles having lately bathed:
As full of spirit as the month of May,
And gorgeous as the sun in Midsummer,
Wanton as youthful goats, wild as young bulls.
I saw young Harry with his beaver on
Rise from the ground like feathered Mercury;
And vaulted with such ease into his seat,
As if an angel dropp¹d down from the clouds
To turn and wind a fiery Pegasus.
In that excellent book, so remarkable for the vivacity of its
descriptions as well as the solidity and penetration of its sentences, the
Wisdom of the Son of Sirach, there is a noble panegyric on the high priest
Simon the son of Onias; and it is a very fine example of the point before us:
How was he honoured in the midst of the people, in his coming
out of the sanctuary! He was as the morning star in the midst of a cloud, and
as the moon at the full; as the sun shining upon the temple of the Most High,
and as the rainbow giving light in the bright clouds: and as the flower of
roses in the spring of the year, as lilies by the rivers of waters, and as the
frankincense tree in summer; as fire and incense in the censer, and as a vessel
of gold set with precious stones; as a fair olive tree budding forth fruit, and
as a cypress which groweth up to the clouds. When he put on the robe of honour,
and was clothed with the perfection of glory, when he went up to the holy
altar, he made the garment of holiness honourable. He himself stood by the
hearth of the altar, compassed with his brethren round about; as a young cedar
in Libanus, and as palm trees compassed they him about. So were all the sons of
Aaron in their glory, and the oblations of the Lord in their hands, &c.
Light
HAVING considered extension, so far as it is capable of raising
ideas of greatness; colour comes next under consideration. All colours depend
on light. Light
therefore ought previously to be examined; and with its opposite, darkness.
With regard to light, to make it a cause capable of producing the sublime, it
must be attended with some circumstances, besides its bare faculty of showing
other objects. Mere light is too common a thing to make a strong impression on
the mind, and without a strong impression nothing can be sublime. But such a
light as that of the sun, immediately exerted on the eye, as it overpowers the
sense, is a very great idea. Light of an inferior strength to this, if it moves
with great celerity, has the same power; for lightning is certainly productive
of grandeur, which it owes chiefly to the extreme velocity of its motion. A
quick transition from light to darkness, or from darkness to light, has yet a
greater effect. But darkness is more productive of sublime ideas than light.
Our great poet was convinced of this; and indeed so full was he of this idea,
so entirely possessed with the power of a well-managed darkness, that in
describing the appearance of the Deity, amidst that profusion of magnificent
images, which the grandeur of his subject provokes him to pour out upon every
side, he is far from forgetting the obscurity which surrounds the most
incomprehensible of all beings, but
‹With majesty of darkness round
Circles his throne.‹
And what is no less remarkable, our author had the secret of
preserving this idea, even when he seemed to depart the farthest from it, when
he describes the light and glory which flows from the Divine presence; a light
which by its very excess is converted into a species of darkness.
Dark
with excessive light
thy skirts appear.
Here is an idea not only poetical in a high degree, but strictly
and philosophically just. Extreme light, by overcoming the organs of sight,
obliterates all objects, so as in its effect exactly to resemble darkness.
After looking for some time at the sun, two black spots, the impression which
it leaves, seem to dance before our eyes. Thus are two ideas as opposite as can
be imagined reconciled in the extremes of both; and both, in spite of their
opposite nature, brought to concur in producing the sublime. And this is not
the only instance wherein the opposite extremes operate equally in favour of
the sublime, which in all things abhors mediocrity.
Light in Building
AS the management of light is a matter of importance in
architecture, it is worth inquiring, how far this remark is applicable to
building. I think then, that all edifices calculated to produce an idea of the
sublime, ought rather to be dark and gloomy, and this for two reasons; the
first is, that darkness itself on other occasions is known by experience to
have a greater effect on the passions than light. The second is, that to make
an object very striking, we should make it as different as possible from the
objects with which we have been immediately conversant; when therefore you
enter a building, you cannot pass into a greater light than you had in the open
air; to go into one some few degrees less luminous, can make only a trifling
change; but to make the transition thoroughly striking, you ought to pass from
the greatest light, to as much darkness as is consistent with the uses of
architecture. A night the contrary rule will hold, but for the very same
reason; and the more highly a room is then illuminated, the grander will the
passion be.
Colour Considered as Productive of the Sublime
AMONG colours, such as are soft or cheerful (except perhaps a
strong red which is cheerful) are unfit to produce grand images. An immense
mountain covered with a shining green turf, is nothing, in this respect, to one
dark and gloomy; the cloudy sky is more grand than the blue; and night more
sublime and solemn than day. Therefore in historical painting, a gay or gaudy
drapery can never have a happy effect: and in buildings, when the highest
degree of the sublime is intended, the materials and ornaments ought neither to
be white, nor green, nor yellow, nor blue, nor a pale red, nor violet, nor
spotted, but of sad and fuscous colours, as black, or brown, or deep purple,
and the like. Much of gilding, mosaics, painting, or statues, contribute but
little to the sublime. This rule need not be put in practice, except where an
uniform degree of the most striking sublimity is to be produced, and that in
every particular; for it ought to be observed, that this melancholy kind of
greatness, though it be certainly the highest, ought not to be studied in all
sorts of edifices, where yet grandeur must be studied: in such cases the
sublimity must be drawn from the other sources; with a strict caution however
against anything light and riant; as nothing so effectually deadens the whole
taste of the sublime.
Sound and Loudness
THE EYE is not the only organ of sensation by which a sublime
passion may be produced. Sounds have a great power in these as in most other
passions. I do not mean words, because words do not affect simply by their
sounds, but by means altogether different. Excessive loudness alone is
sufficient to overpower the soul, to suspend its action, and to fill it with
terror. The noise of vast cataracts, raging storms, thunder, or artillery,
awakes a great and awful sensation in the mind, though we can observe no nicety
or artifice in those sorts of music. The shouting of multitudes has a similar
effect; and, by the sole strength of the sound, so amazes and confounds the
imagination, that, in this staggering and hurry of the mind, the
best-established tempers can scarcely forbear being borne down, and joining in
the common cry, and common resolution of the crowd.
Suddenness
A SUDDEN beginning or sudden cessation of sound of any
considerable force, has the name power. The attention is roused by this; and
the faculties driven forward, as it were, on their guard. Whatever, either in
sights or sounds, makes the transition from one extreme to the other easy,
causes no terror, and consequently can be no cause of greatness. In everything
sudden and unexpected, we are apt to start; that is, we have a perception of
danger, and our nature rouses us to guard against it. It may be observed that a
single sound of some strength, though but of short duration, if repeated after
intervals, has a grand effect. Few things are more awful than the striking of a
great clock, when the silence of the night prevents the attention from being too
much dissipated. The same may be said of a single stroke on a drum, repeated
with pauses; and of the successive firing of cannon at a distance. All the
effects mentioned in this section have causes very nearly alike.
Intermitting
A LOW, tremulous, intermitting sound, though it seems in some
respects opposite to that just mentioned, is productive of the sublime. It is
worth while to examine this a little. The fact itself must be determined by
every man¹s own experience and reflection. I have already observed, that night
increases our terror, more perhaps than anything else; it is our nature, when
we do not know what may happen to us, to fear the worst that can happen; and
hence it is, that uncertainty is so terrible, that we often seek to be rid of
it, at the hazard of certain mischief. Now, some low, confused, uncertain
sounds, leave us in the same fearful anxiety concerning their causes, that no
light, or an uncertain light, does concerning the objects that surround us.
Quale per incertam lunam sub luce maligna
Est iter in sylvis.‹
‹A faint shadow of uncertain light,
Like as a lamp, whose life doth fade away;
Or as the moon clothed with cloudy night
Doth show to him who walks in fear and great affright.
SPENSER.
But light now appearing and now leaving us, and so off and on, is
even more terrible than total darkness: and a sort of uncertain sounds are,
when the necessary dispositions concur, more alarming than a total silence.
The Cries of Animals
SUCH sounds as imitate the natural inarticulate voices of men, or
any animals in pain or danger, are capable of conveying great ideas; unless it
be the well-known voice of some creature, on which we are used to look with
contempt. The angry tones of wild beasts are equally capable of causing a great
and awful sensation.
Hinc exaudiri gemitus iræque leonum
Vincla recusantum, et sera sub nocte rudentum;
Setigerique sues, atque in præsepibus ursi
Sævire; et formæ magnorum ululare luporum.
It might seem that these modulations of sound carry some connexion
with the nature of the things they represent, and are not merely arbitrary;
because the natural cries of all animals, even of those animals with whom we
have not been acquainted, never fail to make themselves sufficiently
understood; this cannot be said of language. The modifications of sound, which
may be productive of the sublime, are almost infinite. Those I have mentioned
are only a few instances to show on what principles they are all built.
Smell and Taste. Bitters and Stenches
Smells
and Tastes have
some share too in ideas of greatness; but it is a small one, weak in its
nature, and confined in its operations. I shall only observe, that no smells or
tastes can produce a grand sensation, except excessive bitters, and intolerable
stenches. It is true, that these affections of the smell and taste, when they
are in their full force, and lean directly upon the sensory, are simply
painful, and accompanied with no sort of delight; but when they are moderated,
as in a description or narrative, they become sources of the sublime, as
genuine as any other, and upon the very same principle of a moderated pain. ³A
cup of bitterness;² ³to drain the bitter cup of fortune;² ³the bitter apples of
Sodom;² these are all ideas suitable to a sublime description. Nor is this
passage of Virgil without sublimity, where the stench of the vapour in Albunea
conspires so happily with the sacred horror and gloominess of that prophetic
forest:
At rex sollicitus monstris oracula Fauni
Fatidici genitoris adit, lucosque sub alta
Consulit Albunea, nemorum quæ maxima sacro
Fonte sonat; sævamque exhalat opaca Mephitim.
In the sixth book, and in a very sublime description, the
poisonous exhalation of Acheron is not forgotten, nor does it all disagree with
the other images amongst which it is introduced:
Spelunca alta fuit, vastoque immanis hiatu,
Scrupea, tuta lacu nigro, nemorumque tenebris;
Quam super haud ullæ poterant impune volantes
Tendere iter pennis: talis sese halitus atris
Faucibus effundens supera ad convexa ferebat.
I have added these examples, because some friends, for whose
judgment I have great deference, were of opinion that if the sentiment stood
nakedly by itself, it would be subject, at first view, to burlesque and
ridicule; but this I imagine would principally arise from considering the
bitterness and stench in company with mean and contemptible ideas, with which
it must be owned they are often united; such an union degrades the sublime in
all other instances as well as in those. But it is one of the tests by which
the sublimity of an image is to be tried, not whether it becomes mean when
associated with mean ideas; but whether, when united with images of an allowed
grandeur, the whole composition is supported with dignity. Things which are
terrible are always great; but when things possess disagreeable qualities, or
such as have indeed some degree of danger, but of a danger easily overcome,
they are merely odious; as toads and spiders.
Feeling. Pain
OF feeling, little more can be said than that the idea of bodily pain, in
all the modes and degrees of labour, pain, anguish, torment, is productive of
the sublime,; and nothing else in this sense can produce it. I need not give
here any fresh instances, as those given in the former sections abundantly illustrate
a remark that, in reality, wants only an attention to nature, to be made by
everybody.
Having thus run through the causes of the sublime with reference
to all the senses, my first observation (sect. 7) will be found very nearly
true; that the sublime is an idea belonging to self-preservation; that it is
therefore one of the most affecting we have; that its strongest emotion is an
emotion distress; and that no pleasure from a positive cause belongs to it.
Numberless examples, besides those mentioned, might be brought in support of
these truths, and many perhaps useful consequences drawn from them-
Sed fugit interea, fugit irrevocabile tempus,
Singula dum capti circumvectamur amore.